Specters of revolt
Specters of Revolt
On the Intellect of Insurrection
and Philosophy from Below
Richard Gilman-Opalsky
Published by Repeater Books
An imprint of Watkins Media Ltd
19–21 Cecil Court
London
WC2N 4EZ
UK
www.repeaterbooks.com
A Repeater Books paperback original 2016
1
Copyright © Richard Gilman-Opalsky 2016
Richard Gilman-Opalsky asserts the moral right to be identified as the author of this work.
Cover design: Johnny Bull
Typography and typesetting: Jan Middendorp
Typefaces: Chaparral Pro, Absara Sans
Printed in Finland
ISBN: 978-1-910924-36-5
Ebook ISBN: 978-1-910924-37-2
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publishers.
This book is sold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re-sold, hired out or otherwise circulated without the publisher’s prior consent in any form of binding or cover other than that in which it is published and without a similar condition including this condition being imposed on the subsequent purchaser.
For Robyn, for the love and companionship.
For Roscoe, for the laughter and imagination.
For Ramsey, for the sweetness and joy.
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION
It’s Always Antebellum
CHAPTER 1
Becoming-Ghost
CHAPTER 2
Beyond Struggle
CHAPTER 3
Unjamming the Insurrectionary Imagination
CHAPTER 4
The Eternal Recurrence of Revolt
CHAPTER 5
A Graveyard for Orthodoxies
CHAPTER 6
The Ferguson Revolt Did Not Take Place
CHAPTER 7
Reason and Revolt: Philosophy from Below
The word “antebellum” presents an interesting idea. The word’s particular historical reference is to the period in the southern US before the American Civil War, but its general etymology refers to the time before war. Technically, “ante” means before and “bellum” means war. Human history reveals every time as a time before war. It is even antebellum during wartime — the present war is never the last war. The war to end all wars has never happened. Whenever there has not been war, or when one is taking place, a future war remains somewhere on the horizon. Thus, times of peace cannot be called “postbellum,” because there is no “after war,” only “before war.” The postbellum may function as a utopian touchstone, a thing that has its uses. Whereas, antebellum captures the sense of a present situation about to be changed by some imminent conflict. For those who dream of a peaceful world, this represents a cynical view, or perhaps, just a view held true so far.
But shifting from war to other modes of conflict and other forms of fighting, this same notion turns optimistic and hopeful. Some formulation like the following captures the point well: If we are not now rising up for something better, we will be. This book is not about war, but revolt.
Happily, there are other ways of contesting reality and relations of power than with the militaries of governments. This book explores and develops the premise that human hope, revolutionary imaginations, creativity, and critique — for however long they’re in abeyance — are always eventually liberated and activated in moments of revolt. Of course, this premise will have to be borne out, and basic terms like “revolt,” “revolution,” and “critique” need much defining.
But entertaining the premise, for the introductory time being, we might think of every moment in between revolt as a time before revolt. Perhaps, instead of “antebellum,” we may speak of “anterivolta.” Like war, revolt against the existing state of affairs also keeps on occurring, yet more than war, revolt embodies and reflects the transformative aspirations of everyday people. Whereas wars waged by states embody and reflect the interests of power and capital, which usually coincide. Inasmuch as revolt comes back, in new forms, in different places, with different stakes and demands, periods of relative passivity, times of quiet, are haunted by the specter of revolt, just as peacetime is haunted by the specter of war.
The title of this book, Specters of Revolt, intends an allusion to two major thinkers separated by a century: First, the title alludes to Karl Marx, who happily announced in The Communist Manifesto, that “A specter is haunting Europe — the specter of Communism.”1 Marx understood that the present was haunted by its future abolition. Second, this book intends to recall one of the greatest works of Jacques Derrida, Specters of Marx, published early into the post-Cold War period.2 Derrida’s study of the enduring relevance of Marx emerged in the wake of the ideological model of opposition between capitalism and socialism which spanned the short 20th century. The short 20th century was defined by Eric Hobsbawm as the period between 1914 and 1991.3 In the 21st century that began in the 1990s, a new hegemony emerged around the conclusion that Marx was now irrelevant, proven wrong, and responsible (even if indirectly) for some of the worst catastrophes the world had known. Against the ascendant post-Cold War opinion, Derrida insists that Marxism
is still necessary but provided it be transformed and adapted to new conditions and to a new thinking of the ideological, provided it be made to analyze the new articulation of techno-economic casualties and of religious ghosts, the dependent condition of the juridical at the service of socio-economic powers or States that are themselves never totally independent with regard to capital [but there is no longer, there never was just capital, nor capitalism in the singular, but capitalisms plural — whether state or private, real or symbolic, always linked to spectral forces — or rather capitalizations whose antagonisms are irreducible].
This transformation and this opening up of Marxism are in con formity with what we were calling a moment ago the spirit of Marxism.4
Derrida is here insisting that Marxism was not killed in the Cold War, but rather, it is awaiting its next iteration, against previous orthodoxies and forms and for an analysis of the changing present. He acknowledges that the ongoing re-articulation of Marx’s critical analysis of capital is a defining part of Marxism itself, which began shortly after Marx’s death with all forms of rethinking the critique of capital and power in ways beyond both the imagination and the life and times of Marx himself.
Derrida observed:
Capitalist societies can always heave a sigh of relief and say to themselves: communism is finished since the collapse of the totalitarianisms of the twentieth century and not only is it finished, but it did not take place, it was only a ghost. They do no more than disavow the undeniable itself: a ghost never dies, it remains always to come and to come-back.5
Considered in terms of a communist logos (as opposed to a “communist government”), we might say that if there is anything sensible in the idea of communism, in its opposition to capitalist society, then the communist logos cannot be killed by collapsed regimes. Inasmuch as Marxism continues to express and address real disaffections about real deficits in present society and everyday life, capitalist societies will never be rid of it, no matter how much they might like to deny its existence, to proclaim its death.
Derrida’s overarching argument is that, while the 20th century seemed to vindicate Marx’s claim from the 19th century that the world was haunted by the ghost of communism, the 21st would yet continue to be haunted by Marx in spectral forms to be determined, to be reconsidered. Bringing the two together, I claim that both communism and Marx do haunt — and will continue to haunt — the 21st century in particular ways that this book will take up directly in its course. However, the ghosts are neither clearly communist nor Marxist all (or even most) of the time. I suggest a broader framework regarding specters of revolt, which give rise to communist and Marxist hauntings, but also, which haunt the world with other ideas about autonomy, everyday life, anxiety, experience, knowledge, and possibility, in ways that often include but are quite clearly not limited to Marxian and communist discourses, no matter how transformed.
In the fall of 1998, I was a student of Derrida’s in his seminar at The New School for Social Research, “Justice, Perjury, and Forgiveness.” Despite the ambitious title, Derrida’s singular focus that semester was forgiveness. He was particularly interested in the notion that to be pardoned or forgiven is only actually meaningful in the face of the unpardonable, the unforgivable. To forgive someone for a minor mistake, or to say “pardon me” when accidentally bumping into a stranger on the street, is perhaps a nicety, a well-meaning mannerism or gesture, but where forgiveness is really needed — where it actually changes human relations — is where (and when) it is given to the unforgivable. In this way, the power of forgiveness depends upon the unforgivable.
Since then, I have maintained a correlated interest in the acceptance of the unacceptable, in the toleration of the intolerable, pairings that indicate a deeper problem; deeper in the sense that humans regularly accept the unacceptable (unlike forgiving the unforgivable). People regularly accept theoretically changeable facts of the world that are, even by their own accounts, totally unacceptable. Adjustments and acquiescence to unhappiness and dissatisfaction are common expectations of a practical life of “doing what one has to do,” and yet, it remains a basic ethical instinct to say that we should not accept a life that does us and others real measurable harm — at home, at work, in school, in society. And yet we regularly do. We do, that is, until there is a revolt against the unacceptable, against the intolerable.
In this way, revolt seems to me a peculiar force of (or, perhaps, toward) justice that emerges in the crisis of the system of the repressed-irrepressible, of the accepted-unacceptable. Derrida’s seminar on forgiveness, much like his famous essay on justice and the law, explored how these things (forgiveness, justice, the law) depend upon their opposites, how forgiveness requires the unforgivable, and how what is just and legal (in French, “droit”) requires what is unjust and illegal.6 We may look upon revolt as a disruption, often vilified as “violent,” that actually comes from the violence of its absence. Powerful interruptions of normal life are typically felt to be and caricatured as “violent” when the interruptions have real and immediate effects at home, at work, in school, or in society. However, the real hope and power of revolt is that it may expose how the cooperative reproduction of the “normal” state of affairs actually conceals a range of unacceptable realities.
Whereas Derrida’s Specters of Marx embodies and reflects a particular historicity of Marxist philosophy in the wake of the Cold War and the end of the Soviet Union, Specters of Revolt aims to think through how systems of oppression are always haunted by revolt, how revolt is the oppositional (and historical and liberatory) theory and practice of transformative aspirations. Thus, while it is true that the worldly impetus for the present work comes from the eventuality of recent revolt and the context of capitalist crisis, it is also true that we can theorize specters of revolt in altogether different contexts.
Consider one distant example: During the gladiatorial times of the Roman Empire, an assorted subset of “criminals” and slaves were held captive and trained as gladiators.7 Gladiators were trained for violent confrontation with other gladiators as a form of popular entertainment tinged with the moral endorsement of public opinion — an opinion taking cover behind the concepts of “punishment” and “justice.” Although some volunteered, most gladiators came from the despised regions in proximity to Rome, those deemed “barbaric” and “uncivilized” enough for the wanton killing of the “sport” — the enslaved, many of them prisoners taken by Romans during conflict with surrounding regions. Their training took place in the ludus, a gladiatorial school, often also the site of their captivity and servitude. The gladiators were “schooled” in severe prison conditions, regarded as subhuman, and forced to fight to the death.
One of Marx’s favorite heroes, Spartacus, emerged in such a “school,” in a ludus of the lanista Batiatus, in Capua in southern Italy.8 Spartacus, the famous Thracian agent of slave revolt in 73 BCE, broke out of his confinement with less than one hundred slaves, making a revolt that led to the uprisings known as the Third Servile War (73-71 BCE). Marx, unsurprisingly, found in this an example of the oppressed “ancient proletariat” rising up against a proto-capitalist oligarchy.9 Despite great limitations and much disagreement in our knowledge of Spartacus and the surrounding history, it is difficult to see the events otherwise. Undoubtedly, the conditions of enslavement gave incentive to the revolt of the slaves.
One could say, then, that this iconic slave revolt was the materialization of a real possibility that must have haunted every ludus. The ludus and the coliseum were equipped with cages, guards, and tunnels, as well as multiple forms of abuse, discipline, and punishment for the maintenance of order and the dissuasion of insurrectionary impulses. It is difficult to imagine the containment and cultivation of such violence, and its deployment for the pleasures of its masters, without the ongoing necessity for a repressive system to guard against the outbreak of revolt.
This suggests a certain hauntology: We do not say that the ancient and abandoned Ludus Magnus, for example, the largest arena and gladiatorial school in Rome, is haunted because of the violence that once occurred there. Rather, we understand that the whole system was haunted by the specter of its possible overthrow, before any revolt occurred, within the energies of the repressed and captive humanity. Such a thesis can be stated in either humanist terms, regarding the dignity of the oppressed, or in strictly materialist terms, regarding the conditions of life. However one puts it, specters of revolt are not new. Revolt is a transformative possibility both structurally and existentially bound to all social, political, and economic systems maintained against the interests of the people they confine. This generality applies broadly throughout human history, and remains widely applicable today in schools, militaries, prisons, impoverished communities, despotic and oligarchic regimes, heavily policed neighborhoods, miserable workplaces, etc. All such locations are haunted by specters of revolt, where the “Spartacus” we wait for is less a person than an upheaval — “Spartacus” as a disruption of the system that can be identified as a feature of the system itself.10 Simply, the basic theorization of Specters of Revolt may well have long predated recent uprisings and capitalist crises, though it is the latter uprisings and crises that motivate this work.
In the years since 2008, certain closures have been reopened by revolt. After the uprising of the Mexican Zapatistas in 1994 opened and set a stage for new forms of revolt against the recently liberated and expanded logic of capital, there were some large but short-lived continuations of Zapatismo in Seattle in 1999 and in Genoa in 2001, as well as in numerous other locations. But then, the closure of capital seemed to stitch things up again, resuming and restoring its hold. Yet in 2008, at the culmination of diverse global crises in economic, social, and political life, Greek revolts tore open the sutures, and since then, we have seen various realizations of the haunting hopes of people in the so-called Arab Spring, in Turkey, Bosnia and Herzegovina, Syria, Brazil, and in Occupy Wall Street, among other places, many of which we consider in greater detail throughout this book.
How does the “Spartacus” haunt and threaten the present? An anecdote: In January 2012, I learned about the re-occupation of Zuccotti Park just as I was boarding a plane from Springfield, IL to New York City to present research at the TELOS conference at NYU and do a book talk at Bluestockings Bookstore. I had not been in New York since the Occupy Wall Street activities began in September 2011, and national news of activists taking over the park again in January opened up the possibility for me to participate in and observe the next iteration of occupations in Zuccotti Park. While I was able to participate in and observe some impressive Occupy activity in Springfield, I knew the first thing I’d do upon arrival in NYC was go check out the happenings at Zuccotti. It was freezing cold on the evening of my arrival, but after stowing my bags in my aunt and uncle’s apartment, I made my way down to the park, only to find it empty, save for about sixty or so NYPD cops. There was a lone man with a sign standing at an outside corner of the park, but aside from him, Zuccotti was only occupied by the police.
I figured I would ask the nearest cop about what had happened, telling him that I’d heard the park had been occupied again. He said, “Yes, they were here yesterday, but it got too cold, so they left.” I asked him, “Since they’re all gone now, why are there so many cops in the park?” He simply replied, “Because they come back.” There was a sense, in that moment, in which the absence of the occupiers and the presence of the police disclosed the hopeful expression of a ghost-like power. The park was clearly haunted by the recently departed spirit of the occupation, and its future possibility. The cops had orders to stay in an empty park, but only because the park had not been fully emptied of its contentious potentiality. After a while, of course, the cops too did leave. But the park remains a transformed and haunted site, a location that can never be stripped of its historic role as the place for a surprising expression of disaffection aimed at capital in the financial nerve center of Manhattan. The park, now even empty, suggests the other side of capital: the opposition to the values, purposes, and effects of Wall Street. Discourses of failure do not change the basic facts of this residual expectation, aspiration, and unfinished business of Occupy. On my visit, power saw fit to go on guard even in the absence of something to guard against. Capital’s spaces and bases must be guarded as they are the physical locations of capitalist activity (much capitalist activity has no such physical location), representations of systems, and even demarcations of time, haunted by what they do.
Part of what enables us to speak of specters of revolt is the recognition of unfinished business from previous revolt. Thus, in Baltimore, MD in 2015 we saw a particular iteration of some of the same disaffections that were expressed in Ferguson, MO in 2014, where we found a certain rekindling of some of what was expressed in New Orleans, LA in 2005, which contained some of what was found in Los Angeles in 1992, which contained some of what was found in Watts, Los Angeles in 1965, leaving out, of course, so many critical incidents and coordinates before and in between. Inasmuch as “in between” also always designates a “time before the next one,” we can speak of the antebellum status of revolt. Specters of revolt haunt in between, that is, both before and after, realizations of revolt. To show this well, clear and certain connections between individual coordinates of upheaval must be made more concrete and far less speculative, and that is partly what this book aims to accomplish.
But there is yet another, and perhaps more important aim of the present book, which one could say was summed up best over four decades ago in a conversation between Michel Foucault and Gilles Deleuze, published under the title, “Intellectuals and Power.” 11 In the conversation, Foucault says the following in reference to the French uprisings of May 1968:
In the most recent upheaval, the intellectual discovered that the masses no longer need him to gain knowledge: they know perfectly well, without illusion; they know far better than he and they are certainly capable of expressing themselves. But there exists a system of power which blocks, prohibits, and invalidates this discourse and this knowledge, a power not only found in the manifest authority of censorship, but one that profoundly and subtly penetrates an entire societal network… In this sense theory does not express, translate, or serve to apply practice: it is practice.12
Foucault’s comments here mark my point of departure. The present book seeks to advance an understanding of the intellect of revolt, not to provide an analysis of revolt. While some analysis of recent global uprisings is inevitably presented in fleeting, tentative passages, I mainly pursue an understanding of what kind of analysis revolt itself offers. I consider the question, also taken up by Deleuze and Guattari, of What is Philosophy?13 In so doing, I try to isolate the most basic features of what might be called “good” philosophy, and then to assess how revolt does it better than professional philosophers ever have done or could do. This thesis, captured well by Foucault, which regards uprising as thinking, upheaval as speaking, is the overarching interest and guiding concern of the present work.
But because revolt is always a destabilizing activity, and because it is animated and energized also by human disaffections, there is often real fear associated with the possibility that it may lead to an even worse reality than the one it opposes. Immanuel Kant was attentive to this possibility in his famous essay on enlightenment, where he recommended public criticism (what he called “the public use of reason”) within the limits of a general obedience (what he called “the private use of reason”), so as to ensure that social and political progress would not undermine the stability and functionality of the basic reality.14 Indeed, one has to take seriously the possibility that revolt may not only fail to improve the situation, but even make the situation worse. Although, in considering that possibility, it is important to assess whether it was in fact the revolt that made things worse, or if political forces of counterinsurgency are mainly to blame. Often, when a revolt goes badly, the repressive apparatus intervenes with its defensive and normalizing violence, and that violence, allied with the ideas of punishment and “justice,” makes things worse. Yet, the normalizing and punitive violence of “law and order” is typically given a peculiar kind of absolution, as if the only violence on the scene belongs to the upheaval, as if the condemnable violence is the sole property of insurrection. Nonetheless, to insist that revolt always improves the situation would be a kind of romanticization, an ideological distortion.
At the same time, nothing is simple or easy in the historical transformation of the world, nor ever has been. Every major advance, including many that we now look upon as obvious and legal, such as the abolition of the transatlantic slave trade, suffrage and women’s rights, the rights of gays and lesbians, had their moments of illegal, courageous, and frightening revolt. Whether we are talking about dangerous slave revolts against the odds of great power, the direct action of Emmeline and Christabel Pankhurst and their comrades who fought with the police, or the Stonewall uprisings against police terrorism in 1969, the risks of repression and political setbacks, and even of death, are serious concerns. Human history does not unfold in one tidy, linear direction. So, how could we know if women and gays will be rounded up and killed, how should we measure the outcomes and aspirations of the Paris Commune or Warsaw Ghetto Uprising, and how could we know if the resistance of Palestinians will result in their total extermination? Hope and fear can mingle in an eternal dance of speculation.
In any case, whether or not it could be worse is the wrong question. It could always be worse and it could always be better. I am not here suggesting we ignore real risks and the possibility of political failure in revolt. Rather, I argue that we must look centrally at the critical and philosophical content of revolt. While, on the one hand, we cannot romanticize revolt, pretending it’s always a full victory, on the other hand, we cannot overlook its philosophical content out of a fear of immediate practical consequences.
For example, in the case of slave uprisings, we see clearly in hindsight that the thinking of the revolt is the better position, and we should keep in mind that present uprisings may well be looked upon with a similar clarity from future perspectives. Yet, to be governed by predictions about future perspectives and possible failure is also highly uncertain, and the politics of fear has long taken sides with the defense of the existing order. Transformative hope sides with the upheaval, however uncertain and rightfully worried that hope may be. This, it seems to me, is all the more reason to engage with the critical and philosophical content of revolt and to oppose the politics of fear that dissuades everything other than the maintenance and reproduction of what already is.
The research for this book began in 2010, when I started working on the first of what would become a series of articles on the relationships between revolt, insurrection, communism, philosophy, and capitalist crisis. These articles were not originally conceived of as a series, but ended up constituting a somewhat cohesive constellation of inquiry that spanned the time and events of the years from 2010 to 2016. What you find in this book, however, is a substantial development and synthesis of discrete researches that were previously published in various journals and magazines, some of which are difficult to find, or have miniscule readerships. The present book begins thinking in the light of uprisings from 2008 to the present, and aims to speak to and anticipate (not to predict) further iterations and occasions of revolt to come. Specters of Revolt is not a collection of previously published essays. I have radically reworked and expanded each piece into complete book chapters, which move them from the vague haunting of each other to a direct linking up, building upon, and theoretical synthesis. In short, this book weaves together years of research on revolt into a new cohesive whole.
The first chapter outlines a hauntology of revolt. We ask: What makes a place, a city, a building, haunted? What is the social and political history that leaves a place haunted, and what is it exactly that does the haunting? Can we speak of ghosts in a materialist language? What do such ghosts tell us, what do they do? To address these questions, we consider the kind of haunting Marx alluded to when, in the opening lines of The Communist Manifesto, he invoked that “specter of communism”: Something that is not quite present, but looms over the existing state of affairs as a danger to it. Can we think, in a similar way, about the specter of revolt? To assist the inquiry, and to show why it matters, I draw on Félix Guattari’s theory of becoming to articulate a politics of becoming-ghost. In this opening chapter, we consider how revolt, as any good ghost would do, threatens to interrupt the constituted present, bringing to light fatal injustices and indignations that have been obscured, dormant, or buried.
In the second chapter, we reconsider the old notion of the virtue of struggle. Struggle has been valorized by radical movements for 200 years, as the name for the dialectical activity driving transformative politics. Struggle and revolution have been associated to the extent that the former is typically understood as both prerequisite to and content of the latter. No transformation without struggle. But should we valorize struggle? I argue for unpacking the other virtues of revolt. Revolt embodies and reflects other virtues of a human life that are more inviting than the hackneyed call for those who are already miserable to struggle and struggle some more. The possibility for activities others than those called “struggle” is at the same time the possibility for making a more desirable mode of action, or many more desirable modes. The old idea of class struggle runs contrary to an autonomist praxis, according to which we might develop new and joyful forms of contestation. Also in this way, specters of revolt are not always defined by catastrophe, as in the ghosts left by death, for they may also be defined by happiness, longing, and revolutionary hope. A politics that valorizes struggle is something no one wants to do; people struggle because they must. Struggle is an apt description of the default position of so much daily life. Therefore, we explore more ecstatic and less insufferable dimensions, impetuses, and purposes of revolt.
Having considered what a specter of revolt is and how revolt relates to happiness and desire, we move on in Chapter 3 to critically consider a prominent form of postmodern politics called “culture jamming.” Culture jamming is clearly not any classical form of political struggle or collective action, and yet it follows a playful, fun, and autonomous revolutionary hope. It appears as a concrete example of revolt by other means, but what exactly does it do? We ask this because, in many ways, culture jamming intends to rethink revolt in light of 20th-century disaffections with conventional notions of revolution. That is, culture jamming is an attempt to rethink revolt so that it doesn’t need to wait for the old class mobilizations that rarely ever come. However, I argue that culture jamming has detourned détournement in the wrong direction, converting a potentially radical situationist praxis into a liberal fantasy that borrows more from capitalist advertising than from Guy Debord. At the same time, we want to learn from culture jamming. What does it tell us about the position of radical critique in the existing society? What does it tell us about communication, media, visual terrains, and revolt by other means than mass action? We discuss and redefine culture jamming so that it may include seemingly spontaneous uprising and collective action, and not only depend upon a tiny cast of atomized celebrity artists engaged in the production of “subversive” marketing spectacles.
Now with a basic theoretical framework for understanding revolt — what it is and how it works — we can consider its actualization in the world.15 In Chapter 4, we consider the promise of what appears to be the eternal recurrence of revolt in the world. The ends of revolt, its eventual ending and lasting effects, do not grasp the meaning and the power of revolt. I argue for shifted attention to the beginning and to the inevitable recurrence of revolt (instead of ending and effects), as the unit of study. This shifts our focus from the political accomplishments of revolt to its critical content. Whenever revolt is not happening, it will. This is how it haunts, this is how it happens. When revolt goes away, it does not go away for good. It goes away, but always comes back. When it ends, if the world is left much as it was before, the revolt is called a failure. But should we accept this discourse of failure? In The Communist Hypothesis, Alain Badiou challenges the discourse of failure that has become a convention when reflecting on the so-called communist projects of the 20th century.16 They were not simply failures, he insists, but experiments that we learned a lot from, and that also included distinct successes. While Badiou is correct to attack the ideological emphasis on communist failure, we are interested in the success/failure discourse as it pertains to recent uprisings, which have been more micropolitical and rhizomatic, and less decisively communist. In relation, specifically, to common criticisms of Occupy and the “Arab Spring,” which accused them of a certain aimlessness, I argue that collective refutation of the basic principles of the existing world is always a triumph. We should consider how specific forms of revolt each and always break through the considerable ideological defenses of the existing world, and how they are realizations of very clear disaffections and aspirations.
The last three chapters of the book turn toward more positive developments of its normative arguments. In Chapter 5, for example, I argue for the necessity of 21st-century Marxism to liberate itself from 20th-century statism. Indeed, there are many Marxian trajectories, including left-communist, autonomist, and anarchist, that attempt to raise the critique of the state form to the same level of the critique of capital. In the 20th century, these theories appeared variously utopian and impractical, but now they must be recovered precisely for their necessity and practicality. How this relates to the interest in revolt is, in very basic terms, twofold: First, revolt remains the way communism works from the bottom up. We must know by now, if communist activity took the form of electoral participation, it would not be communist. Marx himself understood revolt as a historical social force from below. Indeed, his interest in revolt, in the social forces of rebellion, far outstrips his attention to the state form. There is, thus, always a certain Marxism in taking sides with the powers of revolt. Here, too, we find support for Derrida’s thesis on the specters of Marx, although in other places than he looked. Second, as we are considering revolt in the context of capitalist lifeworlds, it is fundamental and necessary to consider which aspects of the capitalist present give rise to revolt.
In Chapter 5, we qualify the haunting Marxism of these arguments by calling for a non-ideological approach that is both willing and able to draw on seemingly contradictory sources from diverse milieus. What we need is not so much Marxism, but rather, a graveyard for orthodoxies. We cannot analyze and defend revolt from some decisively Marxist or anarchist position because revolt does not and will not always conform to our worldviews. If we insist on a Marxist or anarchist interpretation of revolt, then revolt will always appear to us to be for what we are for, which guarantees a misreading of events and bad analysis guided by ideology. And yet, we cannot simply avert our eyes from the abused source materials of past great thinkers, because there is a vast body of resources we can make new use of, if only we will allow ourselves to do so. Rather than the guidance of ideology, we should be guided by the open questioning of revolt. In fact, I argue that new global uprisings can instruct and reveal new readings of our classical and canonical sources.
In Chapter 6, “The Ferguson Revolt Did Not Take Place,” I present a short consideration of the uprisings in impoverished black communities that took place in the US in 2014 and 2015. The chapter owes its brevity to the source material it detourns, Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari’s even shorter essay, “May ’68 Did Not Take Place.”17 The purpose of Chapter 6 is to confront and discuss race and class in the US, set within the context and history of black oppression and black revolt. While this book is not about the US, this chapter takes the opportunity to think through some recent and particularly intense uprisings against police brutality, racism, and classism. But Chapter 6 makes only a brief encounter with its complex and important subject matter, in order to (1) bring attention to the ongoing problem of racism and (2) link recent revolt in the US to past and future articulations of the struggles against racism within capitalist society. These are the particular aims of the chapter, worked out with all due modesty in relation to current and important events in the real world of revolt. However, Chapter 6 also serves the more general and overarching purpose of demonstrating the kind of analysis that my theory of revolt yields and recommends. The chapter is, in fact, an application of the general theory of the book to a reading of actual events in the world.
Finally, Chapter 7 brings a thread that runs through every chapter of this book to its full fruition. Our culminating and concluding arguments focus centrally on the intellect of revolt and philosophy from below. As a whole, Specters of Revolt defends revolt not so much for what it permanently changes in the world, but rather, for what it says, for how it speaks, in short, for its communicative power. In this final chapter, I argue that revolt, as philosophy from below, carries and conveys more critical content than what is conventionally called philosophy. Some days or weeks of uprising in Ferguson or Baltimore contain and communicate more critical content than a book comprised of years of research on the same subjects (including the present one). This does not demean or degrade the book, but rather, positions events as the primary sources on which good books depend.
Throughout history, we can find a defining vision of philosophy as a discursive and dialectical force against the justice and reality of the existing world. There is indeed a long list of philosophers who were openly critical of professional philosophy, dating back at least to Socrates. So, how else is philosophy done, and who else does it? I argue that revolt appears as a modality of philosophy, what we may call “philosophy from below.”
To theorize revolt as “philosophy from below,” it is necessary to refute its conventional vilification as irrational and violent. Rather than making an intellectual analysis of revolt, we try to comprehend revolt as intellectual analysis itself. It is an overarching contention of this book that professional thinkers have more to learn from insurrectionary movements than they have to teach them. Throughout, we aim to take seriously the communicative content of recent revolts, from Greece, to North Africa, to Wall Street, to Turkey, to Brazil, to Ferguson, to Baltimore, and elsewhere.18
The recurrence of revolt has been faster, with less time between global uprisings in the years from 2008 to 2016. Nonetheless, a case needs to be made for the affective and rational content of these movements, which are still often characterized as violent and senseless. And we must go farther. Our goal is to move from the mere appreciation of the affective and rational dimensions of upheaval, to a close reading of its philosophical content. Occupied buildings and public squares, and yes, even riots, typically do more to throw the reality and justice of the world into question than the work of professional philosophers does.
Although I define and distinguish various forms of social upheaval later on, especially (but not only) in Chapters 3, 6, and 7, a brief qualification about riots is useful here. A riot may well be part of a revolt, but it is not always a revolt in-and-of-itself. By riot, we typically mean some wave of illegal group activity that usually involves confrontations with police and property destruction. A riot can be motivated by many things, including nihilist thrill, football hooliganism, or the visceral excitement of blackout looting, lawbreaking, etc. What makes riot an open question is that it does not always or self-consciously express a clearly legible philosophical content, at least not on its face.
But I want to resist two tendencies in thinking about riots. First, I do not regard them as “anti-social behavior.” To the contrary, riots are distinctly social in that they are carried out by groups of people within society who act out together in the upheaval. They are, in fact, more “social” than reading this book. That does not mean they are good. To say something is social is not to defend it. Second, I claim that although riots do not necessarily or self-consciously express a politics of any kind, they do likely contain some political and philosophical content that can be accessed eventually. Whether or not we endorse riots in general is a bad question. I neither endorse nor condemn riots categorically, and of course, we must criticize what needs criticizing. I argue instead that basic understanding demands us to consider why a riot breaks out, how it relates to revolt against the existing state of affairs, and what it communicates about the social situation.
Philosophy has never produced a new world directly, but when it is good, philosophy produces epiphanies about the world, suggesting its transformation. Philosophy is the practical activity of working out the difference and distance between what is and what ought to be. Perhaps the best philosophers do not carry out their work in books and articles. Since the Greek uprisings of 2008, we have seen that the most important philosophy of our time is not written down, but acted out. What economic crises, social instability, and political impasses tell us today is that we still need epiphanies about the world and its necessary transformation. Perhaps we will always be at that historical juncture, or should be. Nonetheless, what we have to do, in so many ways, is to participate in the production of epiphanies, or in the moments of their realization. Epiphany, I argue, is a crucial part of what is called revolution.
1 Marx, Karl, The Communist Manifesto, trans. Samuel Moore (New York: International Publishers, 1994), p. 8.
2 Derrida, Jacques, Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning and the New International, trans. Peggy Kamuf (New York and London: Routledge, 1994).
3 Hobsbawm, Eric, Age of Extremes: A History of the World, 1914-1991 (New York: Vintage Books, 1996).
4 Derrida, Jacques, Specters of Marx (New York: Routledge, 1994), p. 73.
5 Ibid., p. 123.
6 See Derrida, Jacques, “Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority’” in Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson (New York: Routledge, 1992).
7 Gladiatorial combat may well go back to the 3rd century BCE. It thereafter became a prominent part of Roman politics and social life. Gladiator entertainment lasted for close to a thousand years, reaching its peak between the 1st century BCE and the 2nd century ACE. It was formally abolished in the 5th century.
8 See, for one example, “Confessions of Marx” in The Portable Karl Marx, trans. Eugene Kamenka (New York: Viking Penguin, 1983), p. 53.
9 Marx, Karl, On History & People, edited and translated by Saul K. Padover (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1977), p. 304.
10 Do not read my invocation of Spartacus here, or of John Brown later, as lionizations that ignore the uglier sides of these men’s histories, for example their infamous brutality and fanaticism (respectively). Although their brutality and fanaticism should be both questioned and contextualized, I never intend to stipulate with “Spartacus” (in quotes), as with Brown later, the names of personal heroes. That is, I do not mean to invoke the men themselves. Rather, I invoke figures of history associated with insurrections in thought and action.
11 Foucault, Michel, “Intellectuals and Power,” a conversation between Foucault and Deleuze, published in Foucault Live: Interviews, 1961–1984, ed. Sylvère Lotringer (New York: Semiotext(e), 1996).
12 Ibid., p. 75.
13 Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Félix, What is Philosophy?, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994).
14 See Kant, Immanuel, “An Answer to the Question: ‘What is Enlightenment?’” in Political Writings, trans. H.B. Nisbet (Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
15 However, it is not until the final chapter, Chapter 7, that a new cohesive theory of the intellect of insurrection and philosophy from below is fully articulated.
16 Badiou, Alain, The Communist Hypothesis, trans. David Macey and Steve Corcoran (London and New York: Verso, 2010), pp. 1-40.
17 Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Félix, “May ’68 Did Not Take Place” in Hatred of Capitalism: A Semiotext(e) Reader, ed. Chris Kraus and Sylvère Lotringer (Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2001).
18 Several recently published books with some (albeit very different) overlapping interest in the theoretical work of revolt are worth mentioning here: Franco “Bifo” Berardi, The Uprising: On Poetry and Finance (Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2012); Hamid Dabashi, The Arab Spring: The End of Postcolonialism (London and New York: Zed Books, 2012); Marina Sitrin and Dario Azzellini, They Can’t Represent Us!: Reinventing Democracy from Greece to Occupy (London and New York: Verso Books, 2014); Brecht De Smet, A Dialectical Pedagogy of Revolt: Gramsci, Vygotsky, and the Egyptian Revolution (Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2015); Brian C. Lovato, Democracy, Dialectics, and Difference: Hegel, Marx, and 21st Century Social Movements (New York and London: Routledge, 2016). Although these books cover very different ground, I recommend them to readers interested in some of the general and defining themes of the present work.
One must, magically, chase away a specter, exorcise the possible return of a power held to be baleful in itself and whose demonic threat continues to haunt the century.
— JACQUES DERRIDA, Specters of Marx 19
Shit will never be the same in Baltimore.
— DEMARCUS ON TWITTER, The 2015 Baltimore Uprising 20
Ghosts are real and normal. What is truly “paranormal” is their absence.
To understand the meaning of this proclamation, we start by defining, or by redefining, its key terms.21
I do not use the term “ghost” to specify anything supernatural or in any celestial sense. Rather, let’s begin with the question of what a ghost, or a specter, does. A ghost may do many things, but its primary activity — the one which distinguishes the ghost as a ghost — is to haunt. To be haunted is to be troubled or followed by the presence of some invisible thing, some unseen entity that one nonetheless feels or knows to be present. Indeed, a ghost may haunt as an invisible presence, or as a scarcely visible phenomenon (like a faint trace), which affectively transforms the context in which one lives or acts. Ghosts are typically understood to haunt the particular locations, objects, or people with which they are associated in some intimate and historical way. All of this is quite conventional to the common definition of ghosts, and yet it is a language that can be used to describe the normal — possibly universal — experiences of being haunted by personal or political history, being haunted by the bad things we have done or that have been done to us. On the personal level, when we speak of one’s “baggage,” or of being troubled by a memory, by a traumatic event, people can often name the specific ghosts that haunt them. Of course, there are other ways of speaking of these things, but I argue that none of them are as useful as the language of ghosts for diagnostic and prescriptive purposes.
We do not have to go out on any shaky limbs to reclaim the language of ghosts from its supernatural and religious captors. Let us consider the meanings of the German word “Geist.” Depending on context, “Geist” can be translated as the English words “mind,” “spirit,” or “ghost.” The word Geist is etymologically closest to the English word ghost. The multiple meanings of the term substantiate Gilbert Ryle’s famous notion of “the ghost in the machine,” which he used to characterize and critique Descartes’ theory of the mind in the body.22 But for a long time, English renderings have reduced the tripartite meaning of the word to “spirit/mind” or to “spirit (mind),” and choosing which one to go with has a complex philosophical history dating back (at least) to G.W.F. Hegel’s The Phenomenology of Spirit, or The Phenomenology of Mind.23 Both of these are titles for the same book that can still be found in English publication today. We cannot fully settle the choice between one and the other title, because understanding Hegel’s philosophy requires both spiritual-metaphysical and rationalist connotations. Hegel’s work depends upon a more robust conception of Geist and resists reductive translation. In cognitive science and neuropsychology, and in the philosophical work that centralizes these, for example that of Daniel Dennett, spirit has fallen off entirely, because science is more confident than ever before that everything that was mysterious enough to be called “spiritual” can now be demystified as some complexity or another of human brain function.24 This reflects a general consensus in philosophies of the mind today.
So, we must observe the tendency in philosophy and science to strip Geist of all its ghostly meaning, whilst even phonetically, the word “Geist” is nearer to the word “ghost” than any of its more common renderings. But there is more than a phonetic force for ghosts left in the concept and meaning of GeistGeist