Table of Contents
The Blackwell Philosophy and Pop Culture Series
Title Page
Copyright Page
Dedication
Acknowledgements
Introduction
PART ONE - TWILIGHT
one - YOU LOOK GOOD ENOUGH TO EAT: LOVE, MADNESS, AND THE FOOD ANALOGY
“Sorry about the Food Analogy”—What’s Your Pleasure?
“What I Knew Was Right . . . and What I Wanted”
The Vampire Socrates
Lambs and the Predators Who Adore Them
“Other Hungers . . . That Are Foreign to Me”
“A Moonless Night”
NOTES
two - DYING TO EAT: THE VEGETARIAN ETHICS OF TWILIGHT
Scene 1. In Which a Reasonable Ethic Is Proposed
Scene 2. In Which a Classmate Brings Up an Unpleasant Scenario
Scene 3. In Which Edward Says No to the Kosher Option
NOTES
three - CAN A VAMPIRE BE A PERSON?
What Is a Person (Other Than Vampire Food)?
What Humans, Vampires, and Animals Have in Common
If Animals Are Human Food, Are We Vampire Food?
Naughty Vampire! No People for You!
NOTES
four - CARLISLE: MORE COMPASSIONATE THAN A SPEEDING BULLET?
Carlisle’s Theory of “Gifts”
Carlisle’s Super-Compassion
Is Compassion a Feeling?
Compassion of a Saint?
Compassion, Caring, and the Cullen Family
The Power of Connections
NOTES
PART TWO - NEW MOON
five - VAMPIRE-DÄMMERUNG: WHAT CAN TWILIGHT TELL US ABOUT GOD?
Evil’s Not a Problem, Because Evil Doesn’t Exist
Evil’s Not a Problem, Because Evil Indicates Ignorance
Evil’s Not a Problem, Because It’s the Necessary Cost of Good
Evil, Transcendence, and Natural Goodness
NOTES
six - TO BITE OR NOT TO BITE: TWILIGHT, IMMORTALITY, AND THE MEANING OF LIFE
More Love and Death
On Losing One’s Soul
I’m Bored . . .
It’s Complicated
NOTES
seven - MIND READING AND MORALITY: THE MORAL HAZARDS OF BEING EDWARD
Does Power Corrupt or Reveal Moral Character?
Benevolence and Mind Reading
Privacy and Mind Reading
Love and the Inequality of Mind Reading
God and Morality
One Last Thought before Dawn
NOTES
eight - LOVE AND AUTHORITY AMONG WOLVES
What’s Free Will, Anyway?
The Wolves, Free Will, and Authority
Wolf Love and Free Will
A Final Worry
Here Jacob Stands: He Can Do No Other
NOTES
PART THREE - ECLIPSE
nine - BELLA SWAN AND SARAH PALIN: ALL THE OLD MYTHS ARE NOT TRUE
Having It All
All of the Myths Are True
Consider Sarah Palin
A Lesson for Serious Feminists
Who Are the Real Elitists?
A Lesson for Feminists
Having It All in Real Life
NOTES
ten - VAMPIRE LOVE: THE SECOND SEX NEGOTIATES THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY
Back in Time
The Second Sex in the Twenty-first Century
A Feminist Subtext
The Price of Existence
NOTES
eleven - EDWARD CULLEN AND BELLA SWAN: BYRONIC AND FEMINIST HEROES . . . OR NOT
You’re Only Young Once, but You Can Be Byronic Forever
Why Byronic Heroes Make Bad Bosses
Jane Eyre: Gritty Governess, Runaway Bride, and Feminist Hero
The Byronic Hero: Now Available in Marble-like, Sparkly Perfection
Can You Still Be a Feminist If You Become a Bloodsucking Vampire for Your Husband?
Self-Exiled Harold Wanders Forth Again; or, Basically, Bella and Edward Deserve ...
NOTES
twelve - UNDEAD PATRIARCHY AND THE POSSIBILITY OF LOVE
The Control Issues of Edward Cullen
Bella’s Mixed Reactions
Edward’s Progress
Talked into Love
Risk and Transformation
NOTES
thirteen - THE “REAL” DANGER: FACT VS. FICTION FOR THE GIRL AUDIENCE
Just the Facts, Ma’am
Bella and “Generation Me”
Twilight in the Desert of the Real
New Moon Rising?
NOTES
PART FOUR - BREAKING DAWN
fourteen - TWILIGHT OF AN IDOL: OUR FATAL ATTRACTION TO VAMPIRES
An Undying Wish
Deadly Transformations
Unbreakable
Bloody Special
Lone Wolves
Tortuous Thirsts
The Not-So-Guilty Pleasures of Twilight
Once Bitten, Twice Shy: Grave Concerns about Vegetarian Vampires
NOTES
fifteen - BELLA’S VAMPIRE SEMIOTICS
The Signs around Tyler’s Blue Van
The Philosopher of Oneness, Twoness, Threeness
The Sign of the Cross
The Signs of a Good Vampire
Vampire Semiotics Are No Guarantee . . .
The Semiotic Waltz: One, Two, Three, One, Two, Three, One, Two, Three
NOTES
sixteen - SPACE, TIME, AND VAMPIRE ONTOLOGY
Kantian Space and Time
Kant, Dracula, and Twilight’s Vampires
Abilities beyond Space and Time: Alice, Edward, and Aro
When Worlds Collide
NOTES
seventeen - FOR THE STRENGTH OF BELLA? MEYER, VAMPIRES, AND MORMONISM
What’s Religion Got to Do with It?
Meyer’s Religion and Its Philosophical Context
Eternal Covenants, Binding Promises
Eternal Union in Body and Spirit
Close but Not Too Close: The Erotics of Abstinence
Returning the Gaze
Nice Mormon Girls and Sexy Vampires
NOTES
eighteen - THE TAO OF JACOB
It’s Always Darkest before the Dawn
No Good Deed Goes Unpunished
Bend So That You Don’t Break
The Dawning of a New Era
NOTES
CONTRIBUTORS
INDEX
The Blackwell Philosophy and Pop Culture Series
Series Editor: William Irwin
South Park and Philosophy
Edited by Robert Arp
Metallica and Philosophy
Edited by William Irwin
Family Guy and Philosophy
Edited by J. Jeremy Wisnewski
The Daily Show and Philosophy
Edited by Jason Holt
Lost and Philosophy
Edited by Sharon Kaye
24 and Philosophy
Edited by Richard Davis, Jennifer Hart Week, and Ronald Weed
Battlestar Galactica and Philosophy
Edited by Jason T. Eberl
The Office and Philosophy
Edited by J. Jeremy Wisnewski
Batman and Philosophy
Edited by Mark D. White and Robert Arp
House and Philosophy
Edited by Henry Jacoby
Watchmen and Philosophy
Edited by Mark D. White
X-Men and Philosophy
Edited by Rebecca Housel and J. Jeremy Wisnewski
Terminator and Philosophy
Edited by Richard Brown and Kevin Decker
Heroes and Philosophy
Edited by David Kyle Johnson
Final Fantasy and Philosophy
Edited by Jason Blahuta and Michel Beaulieu
To Twilight fans of all ages, both living and undead.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Supernatural Humans We Can’t Live Without
Jeremy and Rebecca would like to collectively thank the contributors of this book for their extraordinary efforts, the team at Wiley who made this project come to life, including Connie Santisteban and Lisa Burstiner, and of course the series editor, William Irwin, for his incredible editorial instincts as well as his pop culture and philosophical prowess—are you sure you’re not a Cullen?
Jeremy thanks his posse for their willingness to put up with endless nonsense and equally endless obsession. Thanks, Dorothy and Audrey. (He’d also like to thank his new son, Lucian Xavier Wisnewski, just because he wants the boy to be thanked in a book—it’s an auspicious start.) Jeremy also wants to thank Meg Lonergan for her patience with proof-reading and her toleration of quirks. She’s been a great help over the past couple of years.
Rebecca conveys hearty appreciation to Laura Smith-Savoca and Jenny Geissler for prepurchasing Twilight tickets, getting to the theater early, and patiently waiting in line with all the tweens and teens so Rebecca could see the movie opening day—what an experience! She also thanks Stephenie Meyer for creating the Twilight universe, Stephen King for being a literary inspiration, and J. K. Rowling for helping to expand the possibilities of the middle-grade/young-adult genre. Abigail Myers gets a shout-out along with Derek Harrison, Ethan Schwartz, Jaime Freedman, and Marguerite Schwartz. Thanks to Mary Conley-Thomas and Eva Schwartz-Barson for being inspirational women who instill a love of story in all their grandchildren and great-grandchildren, and last but certainly not least, Gary, Bob, and Bell for all you do!
INTRODUCTION
Undead Wisdom
Freud once claimed that love and death mark the driving forces of human existence. Having fallen in love with the undead of Twilight, we might well say the same thing about this vampire tale. The Twilight books confront love and death, and so much more, in a way that facilitates a strange recognition—that the dead are indeed wise, and that they are sometimes wise in matters of the heart, even when that heart doesn’t beat. The strange beauty of Twilight lies here, as elsewhere: we are all faced with death, and we all desire to love. These two facts—one deeply unpleasant, the other quite pleasant—are evident in Twilight. This makes for great reading, and as you will soon see, it also provides great philosophical opportunities.
Death is everywhere. It is between any two syllables, waiting to choke the final breath out of you. It is a force like no other: inescapable, ineffable, and absolute—at least for mere mortals. Death captivates. It haunts. The thought that somehow death might not master us enchants the mind until we find ourselves drawn again and again to the hope that we might escape our fate—by being made immortal vampires, or finding an afterlife, or through a scientific “cure” for death. There is little as powerful as the thought of death, and probably little that motivates us in the way that our mortality does.
Except perhaps love. The existentialist philosopher Albert Camus (1913-1960) once claimed that the only real philosophical question was whether or not to kill yourself in the face of an absurd world. The writer Tom Robbins thinks one can only answer this question with one even more basic: Are you able to love? For love, Robbins suggests, is the only thing that makes life worth living. Love allows us to see things we could never see without it. It shapes our perceptions of the world and enables us to be open to deep, meaningful experiences. It can change a humdrum little town in Washington into a world of wonder.
In the world of Twilight, death is not inevitable, and the purest form of love seems to have been found. Such a world not only allows an exploration of the human condition—facing our deepest and darkest fears, as well as our highest hopes. It also demands that we explore our condition—and there is no better companion for such an exploration than philosophy.
The Twilight saga is full of love and death, as well as a host of other topics central to the way we understand ourselves and navigate the world. Philosophical issues permeate the pages of the Twilight books. Bella and Edward are a mirror for our greatest fears and hopes—for all that can go right with our lives and all that can go wrong. They are the human condition writ large, there for our reflection and exploration.
Perhaps surprisingly, we have a lot to learn from the undead, as well as from the way they relate to the living—about ourselves, our experiences, and our relationships with other people. This book aims to help you with just that, asking such questions as: What is the nature of love? Is death something to be feared? How should feminists react to Bella Swan? Is there a moral obligation to be vegetarian? What is it like to experience the world as a vampire? What does it mean to be a person? How free are we?
Forks, Washington, is a small town; unfortunately, minds can be very small places, too. But philosophy has a way of opening up both: It allows us to see what we hadn’t seen before and allows us to explore issues we might not otherwise explore. Only literature rivals philosophy in this capacity, making our examination of the Twilight saga the perfect place for literature and philosophy to meet.
So whether you’re a fan of Edward Cullen or Jacob Black, believe Bella a fool or a romantic, or are a vegan or a carnivore, keep reading! You’ll enjoy chapters on everything from why we love vampires to how Edward is a Byronic hero to the Tao of Jacob, and much more.
PART ONE
TWILIGHT
one
YOU LOOK GOOD ENOUGH TO EAT: LOVE, MADNESS, AND THE FOOD ANALOGY
George A. Dunn
There is always a bit of madness in loving. But there is also always a bit of reason in madness.
—Friedrich Nietzsche1
Edward Cullen is doomed. The new girl sitting next to him in biology class looks and—to make matters even worse—smells good enough to eat. In fact, in the century or so he’s been stalking the Earth, Edward has never before inhaled a fragrance quite so intoxicating. His nostrils have in their delirium taken the rest of his brain hostage. His sanity is on its way to becoming a dim memory, along with all that gentlemanly self-restraint he’s worked so long and hard to cultivate. All he can think about is what he’d like to do with this girl once he gets her alone—and how he can make that happen. Blinded and blindsided by this sudden upsurge of appetite, he’s able to regain control of himself just long enough to bolt out the door and drive to Alaska, where a couple of days of cool mountain air does the work of a long, cold shower, sobering him up and chilling him out.
Philosophy requires a fearless dedication to the truth, so let’s be completely honest with each other right here at the outset: Who among us can’t relate to this experience? Not that your designs on that scrumptious cupcake seated next to you in biology class (or whatever class it was) were exactly the same as Edward’s. Heaven forbid! But there’s not a soul among us who doesn’t have at least some appreciation of what this poor guy is going through. Who hasn’t been ambushed by a desire that strikes with such abrupt force that it becomes nearly impossible to hide its presence, let alone to resist being yanked in whatever direction it wants us to go? Protest all you like, but I think you know exactly what I’m talking about. But if you insist on denying that you’ve ever been slapped silly by a sudden rush of desire, then the kindest thing I can say is that you’re probably not a very promising candidate for the study of philosophy—at least not according to the ancient Greek philosopher Plato (428-348 BCE), whom we shall be meeting shortly.
“Sorry about the Food Analogy”—What’s Your Pleasure?
On first glance, Edward’s experience seems to be something entirely unique to members of his species, since it’s the smell of Bella Swan’s blood that arouses him and there’s nothing figurative about his desire to consume her. “Sorry about the food analogy,” he says to Bella when, in his clumsy attempt to explain his boorish behavior toward her on the day they meet, he ends up comparing her to ice cream.2 Of course, for most of us this really would be no more than an analogy. The delectable eye candy sitting next to you in class wasn’t really a cupcake, and you probably didn’t literally want to take a bite out of the apple of your eye. But there’s something a bit disingenuous about Edward calling his food reference an “analogy,” since he really did want to make a meal of Bella.
Edward’s experience isn’t entirely strange to us, because erotic and romantic longings really do seem to share something in common with physical hunger. And who can doubt that this food analogy—the way that a vampire feeding on his victim can serve as a metaphor for an amorous conquest—accounts for a considerable part of the eroticism of vampire fiction? What else could it be? There’s nothing inherently sexy about being hundreds of years old (or even Edward’s more tender age of only one hundred and eighteen) and always maintaining the temperature of a corpse. But there is something undeniably erotic and intimate about the way a vampire feeds, not to mention the seductive animal magnetism he exudes, through which he effortlessly charms his victims into surrendering their wills and baring their throats. Of course, in the Twilight saga, it’s Bella who’s incessantly trying to wear down Edward’s rock-ribbed resistance. But the Cullen boy is a peculiarly honorable bloodsucker.
In any case, it can’t be an accident that the language of food offers such a rich and felicitous store of metaphors for describing our experience in the seemingly very different domain of sex and romance. No doubt this fact is in part because eating is one of life’s most intensely sensual pleasures. We delight in the appearance, aroma, and taste of our food. Our muscles engage in the agreeably sensuous activities of biting, chewing, and swallowing each tasty morsel. Once we’ve reduced our food to a pulp and pushed it down the esophagus, our contented stomach repays us for the boon via brain boost, radiating a feeling of profound satisfaction to the rest of the body. Each step of the process brings its own distinctive form of pleasure, so it’s with good reason that eating, along with drinking, is closely associated with being merry. For newborns, both human and vampire, the sensual pleasure of feeding offers us our earliest experience of gratification, securing a place for eating as one of our principle paradigms of deep carnal joy. And by a happy coincidence, eating is also the principal activity through which the joyful pulse of life’s vitality is sustained. We eat in obedience to the commands of nature, and nature rewards our obedience by making eating a genuine pleasure. Our sexual appetite is like this, too—nature’s need is our delight. In both hunger and erotic desire, the force of biology finds a powerful ally in the lure of pleasure.
Of course, the analogy isn’t perfect. The activity of eating ends up destroying the object of our enjoyment—or at least putting an end to its existence as an independently existing entity by transforming it into part of our own flesh. Lovers, on the other hand, never literally become one flesh, however tightly they cling to each other. Nonetheless, the world is full of predatory amorists who exploit others in much the same way the rest of us gobble down our meals, showing as little regard for the welfare of their partners as the lion shows for the lamb.
But even if we follow the chivalrous example of Edward—the lion who fell in love with the lamb—and recognize that our beloved has needs and interests of her own that set a limit to how far we can go in indulging our desires, it remains true that every form of sensual enjoyment resembles somewhat the pleasures of eating.3 Enjoyment is always a matter of “imbibing” or being “filled” with sensations that are essentially private or solitary in nature, even when the source of enjoyment is a shared activity like lovemaking. Moreover, we can get so swept up in a flood of pleasure that nothing beyond our present enjoyment seems to matter. Even gentlemanly Edward has to admit that his craving for Bella’s company is essentially selfish, motivated by a desire to feast on her beauty and fragrance, a voluptuous banquet for the sake of which he’s willing to put his beloved at mortal risk.4
“What I Knew Was Right . . . and What I Wanted”
The cover of the first book of the Twilight saga depicts outstretched hands cupping a bright red apple, bringing to mind another famous connection between the alimentary and the amorous that’s deeply embedded in Western consciousness. Most of us are familiar with the story of the Fall of Humanity found in Genesis, the first book of the Bible, which narrates how the first man and woman lost their original childlike innocence and were expelled from paradise as a result of disobeying God’s command not to eat the fruit of “the tree of the knowledge of good and evil” (Genesis 2:17). The Bible, of course, never explicitly identifies the “forbidden fruit” as an apple. But perhaps because apples figured so prominently in Greek mythology as catalysts of desire and discord, someone must have assumed that an apple also was the most likely culprit in the Genesis story, and the idea stuck.5 The Bible also never directly implicates lust as a factor in the Fall. But that didn’t deter many early Christian theologians from insisting that the “knowledge of good and evil” imparted by the forbidden fruit had something to do with carnal knowledge , an interpretation supported by Adam and Eve’s sudden discovery of their nakedness upon partaking of the fruit.6 Consequently, forbidden desire has been associated ever since with taking a big juicy bite out of an apple.
When medieval Christian theologians such as Thomas Aquinas (1224-1274) contemplated that apple, they believed it was alerting us to the dangers of what they called concupiscentia , or “concupiscence.” That was their word for the perfectly natural and spontaneous movement of desire toward pleasurable things, like food and sex. Of course, there’s nothing inherently bad about these objects of desire. In fact, Aquinas insisted they were necessary and good, but—and this is a crucial qualification—only as long as we seek them not solely for pleasure but rather for the sake of the purposes for which he believed God intended them, such as nourishing our bodies and reproducing the species. Allowed to operate outside the constraints of conscience and reason, concupiscent desires become tinder for sins like lust and gluttony. Aquinas classified concupiscence as a form of love, but distinguished it from friendly affection in that the object of concupiscence “is loved, not that any good may come to it, but that it may be possessed.”7 Our desire to eat is concupiscent since we are interested in only the nutrients and enjoyment we can take for ourselves. Erotic desires are concupiscent too, since they aim at our own pleasure.
Concupiscent desires are powerful, pleasurable, and—in the opinion of Aquinas and other Christian moralists—nothing but trouble when they come to dominate the personality. Not only do they incline us toward immoderate and harmful forms of self-indulgence, but when we start to view other people exclusively through the distorting lens of concupiscence, we end up reducing them to mere objects to be consumed or enjoyed. And that’s pretty much how we’re viewed by most vampires outside the Cullen clan. “Happy Meals on legs” is the description of human beings favored by Spike from Buffy the Vampire Slayer—another vampire partial to food analogies. 8 For a frightening picture of how Aquinas might have imagined pure, unbridled “concupiscence on legs,” we need only consider the newborn vampires depicted in Eclipse. They are, as Edward puts it, “[b]loodthirsty, wild, out of control.”9 If these frenzied, amoral appetites run amok are what desire tends to become when left unsupervised by our better rational nature, then let’s man those embattled ramparts of reason.
Edward found himself teetering atop those ramparts one night in Bella’s bedroom. Earlier that day he had discovered he had a potential rival in Mike Newton, and the resultant feelings of jealousy inflamed his desire for Bella to the point that breaking and entering seemed a reasonably good idea. That night he made his first of what were to become his nightly forays into Bella’s bedroom to spy on his beloved while she slept. He later explained to Bella what was going through his head that first night: “I wrestled all night, while watching you sleep, with the chasm between what I knew was right, moral, ethical, and what I wanted. I knew that if I continued to ignore you as I should, or if I left for a few years, till you were gone, that someday you would say yes to Mike, or someone like him.”10
We all know that it isn’t Mike Newton—or even someone very much like him—who would have claimed Bella’s heart if Edward hadn’t come along. But however mistaken Edward may have been about his competition, his wrenching internal struggle was very real. Aquinas undoubtedly would have described it as a battle between concupiscence (“what I wanted”) and conscience (“what I knew was right”). The tremendous power of concupiscence is demonstrated by the fact that hearing his name muttered by Bella in her sleep was all it took to persuade him to chuck conscience aside and go for the apple.
The Vampire Socrates
After all this talk about wanton appetites inducing us to do things that are stupid and wrong, we’re ready at last to make the acquaintance of Plato, one of the greatest philosophers of all time, to ponder the problem of desire. One of the big recurring themes of Plato’s philosophy was the phenomenon the Greeks knew as erôs, a word with a meaning that overlaps to some extent with the Latin concupiscentia but carries an even stronger connotation of irrationality. Erôs is the Greek word for passionate desire, typically, but not necessarily, sexual in nature and frequently associated with madness. For example, when the ancient Greek historian Thucydides (460-395 BCE) described the lust for the overseas empire that gripped the citizens of Athens when they set their sights on conquering the island of Sicily, he referred to it as their erôs, suggesting that this excessive passion crippled their judgment and led directly to their disastrous defeat at the hands of the Spartans in the Peloponnesian war.11
We might compare the Athenian’s foolhardy expedition to another—and particularly foul—expression of erôs that we encounter in the Twilight saga: James’s single-minded obsession with tracking and killing Bella, which also tempts him to engage in reckless behavior through which he courts his own ruin. Most often, erôs referred to the passion of being in love or to intense carnal lust. But as we learn from the examples of Edward, Bella, Jacob Black, Leah Clearwater, and other frequently unhappy residents of Forks and La Push, even the seemingly more benign forms of erôs can addle the mind and wreak havoc on the emotions.
No wonder, then, that some Greek thinkers regarded erôs as a menace. With the premium that philosophers place on reason and the reputation of erôs as a force of irrationality, we might expect the philosopher Plato to be among those cautioning us not to let erôs gain so much as a toehold in our souls. But au contraire! Plato, while never denying that erôs could be a form of madness, held the surprising view that madness wasn’t necessarily a bad thing, even claiming that “the greatest of all good things come to us through madness, provided the madness is divinely given.”12 These are words that Plato attributed to Socrates (470-399 BCE), a fellow philosopher whom many believed exhibited more than a slight touch of madness himself and whom Plato featured as the principle interlocutor (or conversation partner) in all but a handful of the nearly three dozen philosophical dialogues that have been credited to him. In several of these dialogues—notably, the Phaedrus and the Symposium—passionate love is a chief topic of conversation, although erôs turns up as a subsidiary theme in many other places in the Platonic corpus, reflecting Plato’s conviction that any experience this overwhelming and universal must reveal something fundamental about the human condition.
Plato seems to have picked up his interest in erôs from Socrates, whom he quoted in one dialogue as claiming “to know nothing except the things of love”—in Greek, ta erôtica.13 Most books on ancient philosophy will tell you that Socrates was Plato’s teacher or mentor, but in fact their relationship seems to have been based on something much deeper, more mysterious, and perhaps even more erotic than that. It would be much closer to the truth to call Socrates il suo cantante, Plato’s singer, in the very same sense intended by the Volturi when they describe Bella to Edward as la tua cantante.14 For Socrates’ words sang to Plato—and not Plato alone—in the same enthralling accents as Bella’s blood sings to Edward. Not that Plato and Socrates were sleeping with each other. There’s no evidence that Socrates slept with any of the young men who swarmed around him to listen to his philosophical discussions, however much some of them may have desired that. In this respect, he appears to have been as chaste as Edward before taking his nuptial vows. As for Socrates’ young admirers, many of them must have felt just like Bella, awakened from the stupor of their humdrum existence by an encounter with a dazzlingly charismatic figure who seemed to many of them downright otherworldly.
One of these admirers was the handsome and roguish Alcibiades (450-404 BCE) who, despite being the most prominent and desirable man in all of Athens, was thoroughly besotted with love for Socrates. Plato described how poor Alcibiades felt so bewitched by Socrates that he accused him to his face of being like the flute-playing satyr Marsyas, a mythical creature whose music was said to leave his listeners spellbound. “You differ from him only in this,” Alcibiades told Socrates, “that you accomplish the same thing by bare words without instruments.”15 But the comparison is apt for more than just the way the impression made by Socrates’ words resembled the effect of the satyr’s legendary flute playing. Everyone agreed that Socrates’ appearance was remarkably, even alarmingly, satyr-like—which is to say he was an ugly old cuss! With his short stature, corpulent midsection, thick neck, bulging eyes, snub nose, and bald head, it’s unlikely that even vampire venom could have done much for his looks. But however ugly Socrates may have been on the outside, his devoted followers were filled with erôs for what they believed was his incomparably beautiful soul.
Although lacking the outer beauty and grace of vampires like the Cullens, Socrates still seemed like a bloodsucker to many. Even the nineteenth-century philosopher Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855), who heard that old satyr’s flute calling across the centuries, wrote that Socrates was to his young admirers like a “vampire who has sucked the blood of the lover and while doing so has fanned him cool, lulled him to sleep, and tormented him with troubling dreams.”16 But whether Socrates was an evil vampire depends on whom you ask. The families of some of his followers—his victims, if you prefer—watched with alarm as members of Socrates’ clique expressed their scorn for things such as honor, money, and political power—indeed for anything other than the pursuit of philosophical wisdom that Socrates advocated as the only thing worthwhile. But that’s just what erôs does to a person. Everything that isn’t associated with the beloved fades into insignificance. Just as Bella, after all that time spent in the company of immortals, couldn’t help but regard her school prom as “some trite human thing” despite what it meant to her human friends, so the lovers of Socrates tended to lose their taste for the things of the mundane world from which they believed Socrates had rescued them.17
In the minds of most respectable Athenians, the strange spell that the “vampire” Socrates cast on his followers provided ample confirmation that erôs is madness. But at the same time, it persuaded Plato that Socrates was right to claim that some forms of madness can be divine.
Lambs and the Predators Who Adore Them
Plato composed a dialogue titled the Phaedrus, named after the young man of that name whom Socrates engaged one day in a long conversation on the topic of erôs. Phaedrus has just read Socrates a speech written by the famous orator Lysias (445-380 BCE), who describes falling in love as a terrible sickness that enfeebles the judgment and causes those it afflicts to behave in a shameful manner. The lover is needy, controlling, easily wounded, unrealistic in his appraisal of his beloved’s merits, and prone to resentment when the affair ends. We might add that some lovers will even enter your house uninvited, spy on you while you sleep, read the minds of your friends, hold you prisoner, and drag you to the prom against your wishes. Headaches and complications are the best you can expect from a relationship with someone who loves you, according to Lysias. Consequently, he concludes that “[sexual] favors should be granted to one who is not in love with you rather than to one who is.”18 Take a more rational approach to hanky-panky and minimize the emotional risks by pairing off with a “sex buddy” instead of some dangerous madman who has fallen in love with you.
Phaedrus is bowled over by Lysias’s speech, but Socrates thinks it’s terrible—not just because of its morally dubious conclusion but also because he thinks it’s so poorly written and argued. After some goading by Phaedrus, Socrates reluctantly agrees to demonstrate how one could make a better argument—more clear, concise, and logical—on the same topic, composing his own rival speech denouncing love right there on the spot. His begins in a way that will sound familiar to us, distinguishing two contending forces that dwell within every human being, each of which would like to run the show.
One of them is our inborn desire for pleasure, the other an acquired opinion in pursuit of the best. Sometimes the two, lodged within us, agree; at other times they quarrel. Then sometimes one, sometimes the other gains the upper hand. When right opinion with reason rules and leads toward the best, we call this moderation. But when desire irrationally drags us toward pleasure and rules over us, we call this excess.19
Irrational desire for the pleasures of food is gluttony, irrational desire for wine is drunkenness, and irrational desire for some fetching beauty is erotic love. And just like the glutton and the drunk, the lover approaches the object of his desire as something to be consumed and enjoyed, heedless of how he may be harming the one he is using for his pleasure. Does that ring a bell? How about this? The lover is crazy about his beloved, Socrates concludes, in exactly the same way that “wolves adore lambs.”20
We’ve heard it all before—concupiscence and conscience, predators and prey, the food analogy. Poor maligned erôs! Doesn’t anyone have anything nice to say about wild infatuation and smoldering passion? It turns out that Socrates does, after all.
Abruptly breaking off his speech in horror at his offense against the gods—he’s defamed erôs, one of their greatest gifts—he launches into a new speech. Recanting his blasphemies, he now offers a hymn in praise of erôs, lauding it as a “divine madness” through which the souls of lovers sprout wings that can carry them to the greatest heights, even to heaven, the abode of the gods. His speech in praise of erôs is a tour de force, recognized today as a classic in the literature of love for both its memorable metaphors and the serious philosophical ideas they impart. His basic insight seems to be that when we love rightly—more in a moment on what that means—some mortal being can become a window through which higher dimensions of reality shine forth. When we see some lovesick fool doting on some clumsy, weak, imperfect creature, lavishing on her (or him) adoration that only a god could deserve, we may think we’re witnessing an act of insanity. What we don’t realize is that this lover may be glimpsing something higher than meets our sensible and sober eyes, something that really is unconditionally lovable.
“Other Hungers . . . That Are Foreign to Me”
None of this sounds very scientific. But Socrates could respond that love is just one of those bewildering experiences that may in the end be impenetrable to scientific reason. That doesn’t imply we can’t say anything intelligent and meaningful about it, though. Where sterile argument and analysis fail, as perhaps they must when we’re dealing with something as unreasonable as love, Socrates resorts to mythmaking.
He thus invites us to imagine the soul as a chariot, driven by a charioteer and pulled by a team of two winged horses, one compliant and well-behaved, the other stubborn and unruly. Once upon a time, before we acquired our physical bodies, our souls dwelt in heaven, where they “banqueted upon” and were “nourished by”—there’s that food analogy again—the unspeakably marvelous sight of absolute moral and spiritual perfection, the likes of which are glimpsed only in a dim and shadowy way here on Earth.21 Here below in the physical realm we encounter many things that seem to be striving for perfection but never quite reach it. For example, justice is a virtue only imperfectly realized in some of our institutions, moderation something we are able to exercise only occasionally and imperfectly, and knowledge something we possess in only the most fallible and imperfect fashion.
Yet we must have some idea of perfection in order to be able to recognize these myriad forms of imperfection. Socrates’ myth suggests that our idea of perfection is a dim memory of our heavenly existence, when we both gazed and feasted on the ideal forms of justice, moderation, knowledge, and other divine realities that have only defective likenesses on earth. We would be feasting on those visions of perfection today if not for a series of grievous mishaps and blunders that caused us to lose our wings and fall to Earth, where we’re now imprisoned in needy and cumbersome bodies, forced to rely on defective senses that distract us from our memory of the grandeur we once beheld.
Socrates explains that in an imperfect world like ours, there’s little that could serve as a reminder of the brilliant spectacle of those perfect beings that once nourished our souls. Even with the acute senses of a vampire, we still wouldn’t be able to discern many traces of perfection here in this lower realm, where for the most part only imperfect things are visible. As Socrates observes, “There is no shine in the images here on earth of justice and moderation and the other things honorable for souls.”22 Lacking the splendor of their perfect heavenly counterparts, the imperfect instance of justice and moderation we encounter here on Earth doesn’t have the power to reawaken memories of the deep satisfaction and joy we experienced in heaven. And so that joy is forgotten—unless and until we fall in love. For there’s one form of perfection that shines in a way that even our feeble mortal senses can’t easily miss: beauty, especially the beauty that shines from some dazzling creature whose presence alone is enough to flood the soul with erotic and romantic longings.
In heaven the sight of unalloyed beauty, contemplated in its pure electrifying radiance, was “the most blest of the mysteries” we beheld.23 But even after we fell to Earth, “we grasped it shining most clearly through the clearest of our senses, because sight is the sharpest of our physical senses.”24 Socrates probably should have qualified that last statement, for while sight may be the sharpest sense for us mortal human beings, the sense of smell is the most acute for vampires. No surprise, then, that Edward’s powerful longings were awakened by a whiff, rather than the more common vision, of perfection. But regardless of whether it’s a beautiful form or a beautiful fragrance, beauty possesses a unique ability to remind us of a joy that lies beyond this world and therefore beyond mere carnal satisfactions.
But because the soul is complex—remember those two horses, one compliant, the other unruly—our reaction to the sight (or smell, in Edward’s case) of earthly beauty can be a tortured knot of conflicting emotions. On the one hand, the well-behaved horse is constrained by its sense of decency from pouncing straight away on that beautiful creature that looks (or smells) like a little piece of heaven. But the unruly horse feels no such restraint. It goes berserk and lurches forward, dragging the other horse and the charioteer along with it, all the while forcing them “to recall the delights of sex.” Only when they “see the darling’s face, flashing like a lightning bolt,” refreshing the memory of “beauty itself standing alongside moderation on a holy pedestal,” do the more orderly parts of the soul find the strength to restrain the rampaging lust of the unruly horse.25 As Socrates describes it, the battle between the unruly horse and the other parts of the soul can be protracted and ugly, but if it ends with that misbehaving beast subdued, “the lover’s soul follows the darling with awe and a sense of shame.”26
This strange myth unfolds one of the fundamental mysteries of love, how reverence for one’s beloved as a token of otherworldly perfection can cohabit with the most flagrantly carnal desires. To love rightly, on this account, is simply to get that unruly horse of carnal desire under control so that it doesn’t rob of us love’s most precious gift, the opening of a porthole through which fleeting glimpses of transcendent beauty can be spied. Edward knows this tension within the soul firsthand. “I wish you could feel the . . . complexity . . . the confusion . . . I feel,” he stammers to Bella.27 “I’ve told you, on the one hand, the hunger—the thirst—that, deplorable creature that I am, I feel for you. And I think you can understand that, to an extent . . . But . . . there are other hungers. Hungers I don’t understand, that are foreign to me.”28
Carnal lust is a desire to feast our senses on the voluptuous pleasures promised by the beloved’s beautiful flesh, form, and in some cases fragrance. We know exactly what it would mean to sate that sort of desire. But Edward’s experience of other, more mysterious “hungers” points to another, more mysterious feast and to satisfactions that reach us through channels other than the senses. Socrates’ myth gives us a language for describing those satisfactions—feasting at a heavenly banquet on the pure forms of moral and spiritual perfection—but it’s a poetic and metaphoric language that dispels none of the mystery of the experience of love.
“A Moonless Night”
But there’s another aspect of Socrates’ myth that we must not overlook. That boiling cauldron of lust that Socrates depicts as an unruly horse is the very thing that rouses the soul to approach the beloved in the first place! Without that troublemaking scalawag called concupiscent desire, no one would ever draw close enough to mortal beauty to detect within it intimations of something higher. Consequently, our lives would be like Edward’s before he got his first whiff of Bella—sane, sober, and steady. Our lives would be “like a moonless night” with little “points of light and reason” but never a meteor flashing across the sky, dazzling us out of our listless complacency, and awakening strange longings.29
Traditional moralists may have a point when they urge us to be wary of our carnal appetites, especially if our appetites turn out to be anything like Edward’s. But Socrates’ myth suggests that we should be grateful for them as well. No doubt Edward is relieved that he could muster enough self-control to resist that “deplorable” hunger that nearly trampled his good sense and morals into the dirt that fateful day in biology class. But, having defeated the beast that wanted to consume Bella there on the spot, he’s probably still very glad that it was there in the beginning to call his attention to the girl who smelled good enough to eat.
NOTES
1 Thus Spoke Zarathustra: A Book for Everyone and Nobody, trans. by Graham Parkes (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005), p. 36.
2 Stephenie Meyer, Twilight (New York: Little, Brown and Company, 2005), p. 267.
3 Ibid., p. 274.
4 Ibid., p. 266.
5 For example, when Paris of Troy judged a beauty contest among three goddesses, Aphrodite, Hera and Athena, he declared Aphrodite the winner and awarded her a golden apple. The other goddesses were such sore losers that they incited the Trojan War and brought about the destruction of Troy. Consider also the role of apples in the myths of Atalanta and the Garden of the Hesperides.
6 See Elaine Pagels, Adam and Eve and the Serpent: Sex and Politics in Early Christianity (New York: Vintage Books, 1989), pp. 27-28.
7 The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas, Volume One, trans. by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province (Paris: Christian Classics, 1981), p. 299 (Pt. 1, Q. 60, Art. 3).