Table of Contents
The Blackwell Philosophy and Pop Culture Series
Title Page
Copyright Page
Dedication
Acknowledgements
Introduction
X1 : ORIGINS - THE X-FACTOR IN THE EXISTENTIAL
I - THE LURE OF THE NORMAL: WHO WOULDN’T WANT TO BE A MUTANT?
The Paradoxes of Normality
How to Be Abnormal
“Normal” Anxiety
II - AMNESIA, PERSONAL IDENTITY, AND THE MANY LIVES OF WOLVERINE
What Is Personal Identity?
Cassandra Nova, Charles Xavier, and John Locke
Bringing It All Back to Wolverine
Jamie Madrox and Derek Parfit
Bringing It All Back to Wolverine (Again)
Be Slow to Judge
III - IS SUICIDE ALWAYS IMMORAL? JEAN GREY, IMMANUELKANT, AND THE DARK PHOENIX SAGA
“Oh, My God. You Teach Ethics?”
You Got Somethin’ Better, Bub?
Delving Deeper into the Mind of Professor K
Let’s Hear from Our Guests, Scott and Jean! (Applause)
“Jean Grey Is Dead.” “Yeah, That’ll Last.”
IV - X-ISTENTIAL X-MEN: JEWS, SUPERMEN, AND THE LITERATURE OF STRUGGLE
The Jewish Question as Mutant Question
The X-Verse and Camus’ Myth of Sisyphus—or, Why Can’t the World Stay Saved?
X2 : EVOLUTION - CONSCIOUSNESS, CONSCIENCE, AND CURE
V - MAD GENETICS: THE SINISTER SIDE OF BIOLOGICAL MASTERY
The Burden of Dangerous Knowledge
Nature, Red in Tooth and Claw
Evolutionary Justice?
The Eugenic Agenda
The Real “Menace” to Humanity
Behind the Glass
A Sinister Purpose?
VI - LAYLA MILLER KNOWS STUFF: HOW A BUTTERFLY CAN SHOULDER THE WORLD
“Nostradamus Reborn as Wednesday Addams”
“The Greatest Power of All”
“Small in Bulk but Surpassing Everything in Power”
“I’ve Got Bigger Things on My Mind Than God”
VII - X-WOMEN AND X-ISTENCE
Genesis-X
Evolutions
Origins
Astonishing ’70s
Generation NeXt
The Ultimate Conclusion
VIII - MUTANT RIGHTS, TORTURE, AND X-PERIMENTATION
Mutants Are Different
The X-Gene
But They Can Look Just Like Everyone Else . . .
Morality and Impartiality: Aliens vs. Mutants
The Duties of Mutants and Magneto on Mutant Superiority
Experimentation without Consent and Torture
Rights vs. Beneficial Consequences
IX - WHEN YOU KNOW YOU’RE JUST A COMIC BOOK CHARACTER: DEADPOOL
Definitions of Postmodernism and Ontology, and a Brief History of Deadpool
Reading between Panels
When First-Person Narrative Text Boxes Go Wrong
Writers, Artists, and Editors, Oh My!
This Is the Last Section Heading You Will Have to Read
X 3 : UNITED - HUMAN ETHICS AND MUTANT MORALITY IN THE X-VERSE
X - MAGNETO, MUTATION, AND MORALITY
“Nonsense on Stilts”
You Can’t Get an Ought from an Is
Are Ethics an Illusion?
What Einstein Can Learn from Xavier
XI - PROFESSOR X WANTS YOU
Be an X-Man?
It’s All about Me—or Is It?
How Badly Do You Want It, Bub?
Once More, with Feeling
Reporting for Duty
You Say You Want a Revolution
Thank You, Professor X, but I’ll Make Up My Own Mind
XII - DIRTY HAN DS AN D DIRTY MINDS: THE ETHICS OF MIND READING AND MINDWRITING
Should We Trust Telepaths?
How Do I Tell Whether I’m a Mind Reader?
How Much Ought the X-Men to Rely on Telepathy?
Should One Ever Mindwrite?
Is There Such a Thing as a Telepathic Affair?
Getting Your Mind “Dirty”
Trying to Clean a “Dirty” Mind
In a (Real) World Like This
XIII - THE MUTANT CURE OR SOCIAL CHANGE: DEBATING DISABILITY
The Medical Model and the Social Model
Jean, Rogue, and the Medical Model
The Social Model
Dilemmas
Curing Oneself of Persecution
The Cure as a Weapon
XIV - MUTANTS AND THE METAPHYSICS OF RACE
Race and the X-Gene
Mutants and Biological Race
Mutants and Social Races
The Difference between Mutants and Race
Mutants as Racelike
X4 : THE LAST STAND - WAR, TECHNOLOGY, DEATH, AND MUTANTKIND
XV - MUTANT PHENOMENOLOGY
Mutant and Human Being-There
On Occupying Space, Phenomenology-Style
On Occupying Mutant Space
Death and Apocalypse, Mutant-Style
What It’s Like to Be a Mutant
XVI - WAR AND PEACE, POWER AND FAITH
Real Peace
Fear, Oppression, and Violence
The Mutant Other
War
Peace
XVII - HIGH-TECH MYTHOLOGY IN X-MEN
Dream Works
Human and Machine
Mutation
The Psionic Mind
Psionic Blocks
Xavier’s Telepathic Probe
Magneto’s Mutant Machina
The X-Men Metanarrative
CONTRIBUTORS
INDEX
The Blackwell Philosophy and Pop Culture Series
Series Editor: William Irwin
South Park and Philosophy
Edited by Robert Arp
Metallica and Philosophy
Edited by William Irwin
Family Guy and Philosophy
Edited by J. Jeremy Wisnewski
The Daily Show and Philosophy
Edited by Jason Holt
Lost and Philosophy
Edited by Sharon Kaye
24 and Philosophy
Edited by Richard Davis, Jennifer Hart Week,
and Ronald Weed
Battlestar Galactica and Philosophy
Edited by Jason T. Eberl
The Office and Philosophy
Edited by J. Jeremy Wisnewski
Batman and Philosophy
Edited by Mark D. White and Robert Arp
House and Philosophy
Edited by Henry Jacoby
X-Men and Philosophy
Edited by Rebecca Housel and J. Jeremy Wisnewski
Final Fantasy and Philosophy
Edited by Jason P. Blahuta and Michel S. Beaulieu
Heroes and Philosophy
Edited by David Kyle Johnson
Watchmen and Philosophy
Edited by Mark D. White
To mutants everywhere
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Superheroic Thanks to X-tra Special Humans and Mutants Alike!
The editors wish to thank comic greats Stan Lee and the late Jack Kirby, the real X-perts!
We’d also like to thank series editor Bill Irwin for his X-vision and X-traordinary editorial instincts! Love ya, Bill! Special thanks go to our beloved contributors, whose lively intellects and creativity help make this volume a superpower-packed X-ploration into the vast space-time of the X-Verse. We also want to give our appreciation to Connie Santisteban, Eric Nelson, and the entire Wiley team for their publishing super-prowess.
As for the mutants: Beast, for being both a science geek and a badass; Wolverine, for being short; Mystique for bringing blue back into fashion; Phoenix Force, for being the ultimate sentient cosmic force of life and death (c’mon!); and every other mutant superhero, either in the pages of a Marvel comic or in the recesses of a human mind yet to begin a great hero’s journey. . . .
Jeremy wishes to personally thank Meg Lonergan, now an old pro at making things happen; she did an X-cellent job helping with the copyediting and the index—keep it up, Sparky! Nico Meyering and Nick Forst read versions of the manuscript and offered some useful initial feedback. Nick gets an X-tra “thank you” for donating his illustrating abilities (and his imagination) to the book. (Nick is responsible for Jeremy’s inner superhero at the end of chapter 17.) Jeremy is grateful to his wife, Dorothy, for putting up with his eccentricities (yet again), and his daughter, Audrey, for letting him play with her toys.
Rebecca would like to send special thanks to “Mighty” George Dunn, Bob Housel, Aaron Fields, Connie Santisteban, Stephanie “Shadowcat” Collins, and Marguerite Schwartz for lending super-vision to sections of the Marvel-ous manuscript. Bill Irwin gets a Giant-Sized shout out for reading countless e-mails over four years with eighties trivia and X-Men pleas. Tom Morris also gets a nod for accepting Rebecca’s first article ever (!) on X-Men in his 2005 Superheroes volume. Rebecca’s sincere appreciation goes to her husband, Bob, who lovingly made superhuman efforts in the domestic sphere while Rebecca typed away into the wee hours of the morning, and to her son, Gary, who has been her comic partner-in-crime for the better part of the last twenty years.
INTRODUCTION
You Are About to Embark on an X-perience with “the Strangest Heroes of All”1
The X-Men franchise has made billions of dollars over the last forty-five years from major motion pictures, animated television shows, video games, and, of course, the best-selling comic series in American history.2 The Marvel X-Verse is a large and diverse place full of complex storylines, timelines, seemingly endless characters (can you believe the first volume started with only seven?!), and—of course—philosophy.
The first X-Men comic featured Professor Xavier, Marvel Girl, Angel, Beast, Iceman, and Cyclops: five teenagers trying to learn how to control their mutant powers, or “extra” powers, at Xavier’s School for Gifted Youngsters. Oh, and, of course, Magneto’s villainous yet relatable character was also introduced as part of the original cast. And right there at the beginning, the big questions were being asked: What are our obligations to one another? What does it mean to be human?
What are the implications of evolution for the future of human (and mutant) civilization?
X-Men comics were one of the first Marvel series to feature female characters as the leads in multiple storylines. X-Women are shown as strong and powerful, equal to the men around them. X-Men comics also developed a diverse population of mutant superheroes that included African characters such as Storm, Native Americans like Dani Moonstar and Thunderbird, and Asian characters such as Jubilee and Lady Deathstrike. Originally, Stan Lee named the comic “The Mutants,” a less gender-specific title, but his editor thought the audience would not understand what or who a mutant was, so Lee suggested X-Men because the main characters had “extra” powers and were led by a man named Professor X. That was also a rather new concept: having a handicapped leader in Professor X, who, despite being wheelchair-bound, is still one of the most powerful, influential heroes in the X-Men series. Here, too, we can see the underlying philosophical spirit of the X-Verse: All of our traditional hierarchies are scrutinized, questioned, and reimagined. The X-Verse is a deeply philosophical place where our world is dismantled, where our assumptions are turned against us, and where, strangely, we see ourselves in ways that only mutants (and philosophers) can show us. So if you’re a human, this book is for you.
Your X-perience is about to begin. Enjoy the ride!
NOTES
1 This was the tagline used on the cover of the first X-Men comic in September 1963.
2 This is more money than philosophy has made since emerging on the cultural scene some 2,500 years ago.
X1 : ORIGINS
THE X-FACTOR IN THE EXISTENTIAL
I
THE LURE OF THE NORMAL: WHO WOULDN’T WANT TO BE A MUTANT?
Patrick D. Hopkins
In the third X-Men movie, The Last Stand, a “cure” is discovered that suppresses the activity of the mutant gene, turning mutants into ordinary humans.1 Storm, the weather-controller, reacts by asking, “Who would want this cure? I mean, what kind of coward would take it just to fit in?” Meanwhile, Rogue—whose touch can sap the life, energy, and abilities of other people—is preparing her trip to the pharmaceutical clinic.
Given the prejudice, fear, and persecution of mutants, some X-fans empathize with Rogue and can easily imagine wanting to be regular people. But other fans, especially those who have idealized or identified with the X-Men, roll their eyes and shake their heads about Rogue’s decision, seeing in it the rejection of something glorious, unique, and desirable. Why would anyone choose the ordinary, the mundane, over the fantastic and the extraordinary? What kind of person wouldn’t want to be a mutant?
Many of these issues revolve around the idea of the “normal.” In philosophy, we make a distinction between the “descriptive” use of a word, which simply points to how a word is neutrally used to explain or characterize something, and the “prescriptive” use of a word, in which the term is used to indicate how something should be. The idea of “normal” can be used in both ways. As a description, it merely indicates that some condition is statistically average, as in, “Normally, humans have twenty-twenty vision,” or, “Normally, people don’t get angry about petty things.” As a prescription, however, it indicates that something should be the case or should be done in a statistically average way, as in, “Her vision isn’t normal, so she needs glasses,” or, “It’s not normal to get so angry over small stuff; there must be something wrong with him.”
Whether the “normal” is a descriptive or a prescriptive idea, though, is a matter of debate. Is it true that just because something is normal, it should be our goal, our yardstick for how things should be? Does normality give us any guidelines? Or, is “normal” merely the way things statistically happen to be? And can we think of ways to make things much better?
What can the X-Men teach us about how the idea of “normality” works to shape and direct human lives? Is normality something to be valued or something to be transcended? Should a mutant’s desire to be normal be congratulated or looked down on? What about our own desire to be normal or to be extraordinary?
The Paradoxes of Normality
For starters, there are only a limited number of ways to be normal: to fall within a small range around the average score for various traits, whether physical, mental, or social. But there are an unlimited number of ways to be abnormal. Not only can you be an extreme from average, but the way in which that extremity manifests can be wildly varied. Whereas you might be unusually talented, that talent could be specific to thousands of different areas—for example, an ability to play the many different types of musical instruments or sports or excel in the arts or the vocations. You might also be specifically deficient in one or more of thousands of areas. Whereas normality by definition requires the appearance of normality, your abnormalities might be visible or invisible, blatant or subtle, beneficial or detrimental.
Here the basic paradox of normality in the human species arises. On the one hand, we are social beings who feel a strong need to fit into a group (even “nonconformists” usually hang out with similar “nonconformists”—goths with goths, emos with emos, queers with queers), so there is a powerful desire to fit within an acceptable range. You don’t want to stand out. On the other hand, we also want to attract attention to distinguish ourselves from others, so that we don’t get ignored. These conflicting desires may both stem from a basic evolutionary pressure: the drive to be seen as reproductively attractive. We want to be normal enough to indicate to potential mates that there is nothing wrong with us—we don’t have defective genes. But we also want to attract more attention than our competitors and indicate that we have some advantage over others—we have better genes or more social status.
It’s a conundrum of the human condition: we want to fit in and we want to stand out. But there are lots of ways to stand out, some ways better than others. Some of these ways indicate to others that we are desirable; some indicate that we are undesirable.
The X-Men are mostly human, although they often refer to themselves as “mutants” and distinguish themselves from those whom they call “humans.” For the most part, they have ordinary human brains and personalities housed in bodies that possess extraordinary abilities and qualities. Not surprisingly, then, they fall prey to all the vagaries of the ordinary human condition, including the desire to fit in and the desire to stand out. But the mutant gene has many effects, and these various effects in the mutant population demonstrate something about ordinary variation in human beings—namely, that being ordinary is largely a safe bet, whereas being extraordinary is very, very risky. When you pull a ticket for being different out of a hat, given the infinite ways you could be different, you run a risk.
How to Be Abnormal
When Storm asks why anyone would want to “cure” mutation, the blue-furred scientist Hank McCoy (aka Beast) responds, “Is it cowardice to save oneself from persecution? Not all of us can fit in so easily. You don’t shed on the furniture.” Clearly, there are distinctions to be made even among the mutants, even among the abnormal. Some mutants can pass as “normals” because of their appearance and capacity to control their abilities, such as psychic Jean Grey or sheathed-clawed Wolverine. Other mutants, however, are unable to pass as normal humans. And even these can be further distinguished. Some cannot pass because of their appearance, such as furry blue Beast or blue and devil-tailed Nightcrawler or winged Angel. Others cannot completely pass because of their incapacity to control their abilities, such as Rogue, who cannot touch anyone, or Cyclops, who can never show his eyes.
This concept of passing—successfully pretending to be normal—is an important and well-documented real-life experience among homosexuals and light-skinned African Americans. It gives the abnormal (the term here is understood to be simply descriptive) the ability to be treated as normal and thus can allow them to confront, or not confront, their own difference on their own schedules.
So within the range of the abnormal, we have a variety of possibilities of responding to the normal. Though exemplified in the extreme by mutants, these are familiar to many real humans as well. You could have an abnormality (the term here is used descriptively, simply to mean “statistically rare”) that is beneficial (say, the ability to heal quickly, such as Wolverine). You could have an abnormality that is detrimental (say, a disability such as Professor Xavier’s paraplegia). You could have an abnormality that is detectable (say by sight, touch, or smell) but is easy to keep hidden, for example, a third kidney, a photographic memory, or Shadowcat’s phasing ability. You could also have an undetectable abnormality that causes distress when you attempt to hide it: say, a minority sexual orientation or social anxiety or Jean Grey’s unruly telepathy. Maybe you have a detectable abnormality that causes distress, such as a missing limb, a deformity, or Nightcrawler’s tail and three-fingered hands. There’s also the detectable abnormality that causes no distress, such as Colossus’s muscle-bound physique or Emma Frost’s beauty.
To understand this more clearly, imagine the range of abnormality represented in a graph—not a two-dimensional graph, but a three-dimensional one, a cube, with the x-axis (width) representing the degree of utility, or how beneficial/ detrimental the abnormality is; the y-axis (height) representing acceptability, or how the abnormality is received by society as desirable or undesirable; and the z-axis (depth) representing detectability, or how obvious/hidden the abnormality is. This doesn’t in any way fully describe the psychological and social complexity of being abnormal (it doesn’t even try to explain how your own personality might deal with being abnormal or specify in what way an ability might be detectable or used, for instance), but it is a start in helping you see what a range of experience you could have. Any trait outside the norm could fit anywhere within this space.
Now you can understand how falling in different places in the space can affect your attitude toward how good or bad it is to be normal. The philosopher Michel Foucault (1926-1984) described the history of the abnormal as beginning with the broad concept of the “monster” (a grand mix of the unnatural and the impossible) and moving on to the concept of the “individual to be corrected” (a more narrow medical and legal idea of humans who need to be fixed).2 Much of Foucault’s historical lesson is about how society handles the abnormal, but it can also be related to how any individual perceives his or her own abnormality. Are you a monster, someone needing to be fixed, or just different?
Storm despises as moral cowards people who would seek a cure for their mutations, but look at her experience and where she fits in that 3-D graph. Her mutation gives her the power to control the weather but is not in any way detectable unless she wants you to see it. The ability has great utility: it can be used for a wide variety of desirable goals. Weather control is mixed on the acceptability axis—some people may fear her power, but given the fact that she has control over it and it is not obvious, those who rate her ability low on acceptance don’t ever need to know she is a mutant. As with many of the mutants, Storm is exceedingly beautiful, with a perfect physique and face. This abnormality is highly detectable but also highly acceptable and useful. In short, her particular location in the 3-D space means that Storm primarily benefits from her abnormalities and can always pass as someone normal when she chooses to.
Rogue, who is seeking a cure, is not so lucky. She is beautiful, healthy, and charming, but her mutation is complicated. She absorbs the energy, memories, and abilities of the people (abilities especially in the case of mutants) whom she touches, harming each person touched in the process. But she cannot control her power. Touch activates the transfer, regardless of her will. So, while in certain cases Rogue’s ability may be useful, it is largely unacceptable and is largely detectable. Although Rogue can “pass” as an ordinary human for a while, she can do so only by avoiding all touch. This makes her seem quirky after a while and eventually downright strange. It also means that Rogue is unable to engage in certain activities that her otherwise very ordinary human brain and personality want to engage in. She wants, as anyone would, to be able to touch. She wants to kiss a boy, to have a mother stroke her face, to hug a friend. Her ability prevents her from having basic human experiences. No wonder Rogue wants to be normal! She is caught in a terrible situation: she has normal desires and needs but uncontrollable abilities that prevent her from satisfying those desires and needs.
Beast is another whose abnormality is not as beneficial as Storm’s. He is blue and furry, so his mutation is highly detectable. Although his abilities (agility, strength, heightened senses) may be very useful, his appearance is perceived as scary, ugly, monstrous. Unlike Storm, Jean Grey, Wolverine, or Iceman, he cannot pass as normal.
Unfortunately, The Last Stand is not as informative as we would like it to be about why a mutant might want to be cured. For that information, let’s turn to the comic book by Joss Whedon, which covers a version of the cure story.3 Whereas in the film, the mutants who lined up for the cure look mostly normal, in the comic book there is a mix of those who could pass as normal and those who could not. Of course, in pictures, you can pick out only physical characteristics, but this is enough. The mutants who line up in the comic have scales, wings sticking out from beneath jackets, lobster claws for hands, and so on. One mutant actually has his face in his stomach, and in the testing lab, a girl has nightmares that come to life and kill those around her.
Perhaps no place in the X-Men universe is this problem of obvious abnormality explored better than in the story of the Morlocks, a group of mutants who mostly have very obvious and unsightly mutations.4 They have chosen to live underground—a realm that befits their rejection by both normal society and mutants who can pass. In one story, the Morlocks have kidnapped the physically beautiful and winged Angel to be a husband and a consort for the leader of the Morlocks, Callisto. One of the Morlocks, Sunder, asks the others why they are fighting other mutants. He finds this strange since “they’re mutants, like us.” Another of the Morlocks, a mutant called Masque who is hideously deformed but possesses the ability to reshape others’ bodies and faces into whatever form he wishes, says, “Not like us, Sunder. They pretty! Hate ’em. Want to hurt ’em!” Masque even thinks of Nightcrawler—the blue-skinned, three-fingered, three-toed, devil-tailed tele-porter—as “pretty” and wants to turn him inside out. Of course, this is ironic, considering that Nightcrawler is one of the mutants who cannot pass as normal. In the comic book, Callisto asks Nightcrawler to join the Morlocks since he is so obviously not human, and in the film X2 Nightcrawler asks shape-shifter Mystique, herself usually blue and scaled, why she doesn’t stay in a normal human shape all the time.
Some people may wish they had a Morlock’s powers, but few, if any, wish to look like a Morlock. Why? Partly because we function with a cultural and evolutionary sense of what counts as attractive and thus find the abnormalities of the Morlocks “ugly.” Also, because no matter what abilities they might have, people know if they looked like Morlocks, they would be despised by normal humans, perhaps even by normal-looking mutants. Angels and devils both have powers, but angels are prettier.
What most people seem to want, then, and this is part of the reason they might fantasize about being an X-Man, is to be different in a way that makes them stand out, but only in terms of being powerful, beautiful, and able to pass when desired. Some people might want to have abnormally good looks, abnormally high athletic ability, or an abnormally healthy immune system, but they would not want anything that inhibited them socially or physically. People want to stand out, and fit in, on conventional terms. How very normal, then, to want to be unusual only if it benefits us.
“Normal” Anxiety
Fantasy and science fiction provide an escape from the normal, allowing us to imagine the richness of a life that is enhanced by having special abilities and extraordinary experiences. We imagine the great and wonderful things we could do if only we weren’t so limited, so ordinary. And it is no mere stereotype that the creators of works in speculative fiction and film have themselves often felt as if they didn’t fit into society, thus turning to worlds in which characters who did not fit in were magnificent and enviable.
It is curious and telling, however, that so much of the fiction about the extraordinary belies an anxiety about normality and about abnormality. Characters routinely lament their special status and give long-winded monologues on how they just want to set aside the unique lives they experience and return to or become quintessential “average” people. We also find that the most evil or dangerous characters are most likely to cling to their differences, despising the normality of others as limiting them to banal experience, as with Magneto’s insistence in X-Men United that mutants are “homo superior” and are as “gods among insects.”5 It’s as if, at the same time that we envy the extraordinary or the uncanny, we also want to express our anxiety about being the outlier, about being special. There is excitement about being unusual, but there is also great comfort in being ordinary—which is often, and ironically, expressed by describing the normal person as having access to some experience that the extraordinary person cannot have (Rogue watching with envy as a mother caresses a child’s skin, or Beast looking longingly at his ordinary unfurry hand when his mutation is temporarily suppressed). Somehow, we want to try to value the very ordinariness of life that science fiction and fantasy give us an escape from. Are we not perhaps trying to comfort ourselves, while at the very same time, escaping ourselves?
But not all of the anxiety about the uncanny and the extraordinary is science fiction. What about the real-world attempt to use technology to change into something extraordinary? Is such a desire understandable, even praiseworthy? Or is such a desire to be met with skepticism, horror, or even condemnation? We live on the edge of a world in which genetic engineering, pharmacological manipulation, and cybernetic implants open up the opportunity for a person to become something like a real mutant. Soon, perhaps, we may be able to alter ourselves to achieve what some fictional mutants possess: greater strength, intelligence, agility, immunity, longevity (though probably not weather control). Is this a bad thing? Is it wrong to push ourselves outside the limits of what is human? Transhumanists don’t think so.
The transhumanist movement wants to use technology to enhance human beings, to push us beyond our biological limits until we become something grander and more transcendent.6 Not surprisingly, transhumanists tend to adore the X-Men and most probably think Rogue is misguided to seek a cure for mutation.
Contrasting with transhumanists are “bioconservatives,” who advocate conserving the normal biological status of human beings. One group of bioconservatives consists of natural law theorists. “Natural law” argues that morality comes from the given needs, abilities, and limitations we have as humans and says that trying to change human nature is the worst sort of pride and arrogance.7
So here we have two groups that already have real-world answers to the question of “Who wouldn’t want to be a mutant?” Transhumanists don’t want to be a certain kind of mutant—not the deformed or the weak or the kind of abnormal that interferes with living—but they love the idea of being extraordinary in all of the beautiful and powerful ways one could imagine. Bioconservatives don’t want to be any sort of mutant at all. For them, the normal is a moral obligation.
But, of course, the “normal” is relative. If we all become extraordinary, then by comparison won’t we end up simply being ordinary again? If everyone can fly, is flying special? This is where the tricky part of normality and abnormality comes into play. When we value something—an ability, a capacity, a trait—for what it can allow us to do, then possessing that ability may be reward enough. But sometimes, we value an ability or a trait only because others do not have it. Compare being healthy and being tall. Everyone could be healthy—no diseases, no injuries—and we would all benefit from being so. But everyone cannot be tall, because “tall” is a comparative idea. You are only “tall” in relation to someone who is shorter than you. Everyone could be 6 feet 5 inches high, but then 6’5’ would be standard, not “tall.” So we need to ask ourselves when we desire something whether we want it because it would benefit us no matter what or because it would benefit us only by comparison to someone who doesn’t have it. The answer to that question partly determines whether we are acting on behalf of all humanity or acting only on behalf of ourselves. If you want to fly, even if everyone else could fly, too, then flying for you is valuable no matter what. But if you want to be able to become invisible only if others could not become invisible, then you are merely seeking a relative advantage. We could also ask a similar question about people’s desire to be normal. Do they want to be normal because being abnormal (in the “greater ability” sense of the X-Men) would impose greater responsibilities on them and they don’t want such responsibilities? Do they want to feel justified in not having to fight evil all the time? Funny. We might obviously be selfish in our desire to be extraordinary, but we might also be selfish in our desire to be normal. It makes you think . . .
So, there are your answers to the title question “Who wouldn’t want to be a mutant?”—people who are limited by their abnormalities, people who are ostracized because of their abnormalities, and even people who don’t want the responsibility that comes with having certain abnormalities. There can be great comfort in being normal, even if it is sometimes at the cost of never standing out.
The philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) once wrote, “Man is something that should be overcome. What have you done to overcome him? All creatures hitherto have created something beyond themselves: and do you want to be the ebb of this great tide, and return to animals rather than overcoming man?”8 Although in context, Nietzsche’s character Zarathustra is preaching about humanity’s religious experience, the general idea is well admired by transhumanists. They see humanity and its current normal range as something to be overcome, something that oppressively limits us. Our minds, curiously not as constrained as our bodies, can imagine what it would be like to be very different from what we are. Is this not obvious in the case of the fictional X-Men? We can imagine ourselves with abilities beyond what we can actually do. The question is, What is our motivation for wanting to overcome man? And equally important, What is our motivation for not wanting to?
NOTES
1 See director Brett Ratner’s X-Men: The Last Stand (20th Century Fox, 2006), DVD.
2 Michel Foucault, Abnormal: Lectures at the College de France 1974-1975 (New York: Picador, 2003).
3 Joss Whedon, Astonishing X-Men, Vol. 1: Gifted (New York: Marvel, 2004).
4 Chris Claremont, The Uncanny X-Men #169 (New York: Marvel, 1983).
5 See director Bryan Singer’s X2: X-Men United (20th Century Fox, 2003), DVD.
6 See www.transhumanism.org/index.php/WTA/index/.
7 Patrick Hopkins, “Natural Law,” Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd ed. (Farmington Hills, MI: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006), chap. 6, pp. 505-517.
8 Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra (New York: Penguin Books USA, 1969), p. 41.
II
AMNESIA, PERSONAL IDENTITY, AND THE MANY LIVES OF WOLVERINE
Jason Southworth
In Hulk #180-182, Wolverine makes his first appearance as little more than a feral man in a colorful costume with no memories of his past or seemingly of anything (in fact, in Giant-Size X-Men #1, he has no memory of the Hulk appearance). The Weapon X stories in Marvel Comics Presents show us some of the things the character has done as an agent of the Canadian government, and Origin gives us a glimpse of the character prior to his time at Weapon X, when he was more at peace with the world.
Over the years, Professor Xavier and Wolverine had very little success in reversing the amnesia until House of M, when Wolverine finally recovered all of his memories. But rather than answer questions about his identity, the sudden emergence of these memories has raised more questions for Wolverine about who he really is.
What Is Personal Identity?
The issue of personal identity is actually a set of issues that are entangled and, at times, may be conflated. The questions philosophers try to answer when they discuss personal identity are: What constitutes personhood? Who am I? And what does it mean for a person to persist over time?
When establishing what constitutes personhood, philosophers are trying to figure out what makes a person a person (rather than, say, a comic book). What properties must that entity have to count as a person? Many nonphilosophers may not think this is an interesting or difficult question to answer, as our common use of the term person is synonymous with human. The case of the mutants in the X-books shows why this is an unsatisfactory answer, as they are not humans—they are Homo superiors, not Homo sapiens. If mutants are persons, then being a human is not a necessary condition (it is not required) for being a person. As you might imagine, philosophers do not spend a lot of time talking about Homo superiors, but we do spend quite a lot of time talking about other animals and artificial intelligence. You might consider whether Kitty Pryde’s pet dragon, Lockheed, and the Scarlet Witch’s robot husband, the Vision, are persons.
When we consider the question of “Who am I?” we are trying to establish the characteristics that make you the person that you are, as opposed to some other person. Again, this question appears deceptively easy to answer. You might think that you can just rattle off a description of your character traits, but the answer is going to have to be more complicated than that, because we can often be described in a variety of ways, some of which might be in tension. The question of who counts as a person and why is one of the recurring tropes of Wolverine’s storyline. We see this when the Ol’ Canucklehead goes on one of his tears, complaining that he is not the animal that some people think that he is.
Personhood and persistence over time also feature prominently in X-Men. Consider the classic story “Days of Future Past” (which appeared in Uncanny X-Men #141 and 142), in which we encounter characters who seem to be many of the X-Men we know (including Wolverine), but in the future. How do we know that they are the same characters? They look the same. This is the standard, unreflective first response people often give to the question of personal identity: people persist over time if they occupy the same bodies. Same claws and pointy hair? Well, it must be Wolverine. That’s just common sense—which, as we’ll see, isn’t always as common or sensical as we might initially think.1 Still, you might say, who cares?
Well, the main reason we should care about personal identity concerns moral culpability. All moral frameworks involve the attribution of blame and praise, and many call for punishment. In order to attribute praise and blame for an act, we have to be certain that the people to whom we are giving the praise and the blame are the ones who deserve it, based on their actions. If, for example, it turns out that the man called Logan is not the same person who committed atrocities for the Canadian government under the code name Weapon X, then he should not be punished for the behavior of that person. Likewise, if the current Wolverine is not the same person that he was in the past, Sabretooth and Lady Deathstrike would be wrong in their attempts to punish him.
Cassandra Nova, Charles Xavier, and John Locke
The philosopher John Locke (1632-1704) argued against the commonsense view that the body is the source of personal identity, using a modified example from the pop culture of his own time. Locke told a story that was essentially The Prince and the Pauper, except the individuals exchanged minds, rather than simply roles. If Locke were around today, he might instead have talked about Charles Xavier and Cassandra Nova. In Grant Morrison’s run on New X-Men (if you haven’t read it, you should be ashamed of yourself), we learn that Cassandra Nova placed her mind in Charles Xavier’s body and placed Xavier’s mind in her body. The Xavier body with Nova’s mind forced Beak (if you don’t know who Beak is, you should be doubly ashamed of yourself) to beat the Beast so badly, he had to be hospitalized, and started a war between the Shi’ar Empire and the X-Men.2 When the body of Xavier manipulated Beak, it referred to itself as Cassandra. Likewise, later in the story, when Jean Grey communicates with the mind in Cassandra Nova’s body, it reports to be Xavier. Prior to discovering the switch, the X-Men naturally believed the actions of Xavier’s body to be those of Xavier. After finding out about this switch, however, they do not hold Xavier accountable for the actions taken by his body. Instead, they condemn Cassandra Nova for them and discuss how to defeat her. So, it seems personal identity is not a matter of body but of mind.
Having rejected the body theory in favor of something mental, Locke tries to determine the nature of the mental thing. What mental properties or characteristics could indicate persistence over time? Locke quickly rejects any type of character or personality traits because such traits are constantly in flux. We’re always trying to become better people, and, as a result, our morality, tastes, and preferences tend to change often. Yet we remain in essence the same people.
By process of elimination, we come to memories as the source of personal identity. Locke does not mean that we need to have all and only the memories that a previous individual in time has had. You have “sameness of memories” even if you have additional memories that come after the memories that you have in common with yourself at an earlier time. So, we would say that Wolverine is still the same person he was the day he joined the New Avengers as he was the day after, since he has the same memories he had the day before.
Of course, we don’t remember everything that happens to us—and some of us are more forgetful than others. Locke isn’t forgetful on this account, though: he complicates things by introducing the concept of connected memories. One memory can be connected to another as follows: I remember a time when I had a memory I no longer have. As long as I can remember such a time, then those earlier memories still count as mine.3 So, even if Wolverine no longer has memories of the first time he performed the Fast Ball Special with Colossus (in Uncanny X-Men #100. I didn’t even have to look that up. I am a walking OHotMU), as long as he remembers a time when he did remember that day, then he is still the same person as he was on that day. Likewise, since on the day he joined the X-Men, Wolverine did not have memories of his encounter with the Hulk in Hulk #180-182, nor does he have memories of a time when he had memories of this, there are no connected memories, and he is, as a result, not the same person who encountered the Hulk on that day.
Bringing It All Back to Wolverine
If sameness of memory gives us sameness of person, then it seems several different people have inhabited the body we recognize as Wolverine’s. Let’s go through the history of Wolverine as it has been revealed to us so far and yell out, “New Wolverine!” every time we spot one.
The known history of Wolverine begins in Origin (2002). In this story, we learn that he was born in the nineteenth century on a plantation in Canada under the name James Howlett. Howlett left the plantation and adopted the name “Logan,” the last name of the groundskeeper on the plantation. He had several adventures after leaving the plantation, first living with a pack of wolves, then with Blackfoot Indians (marrying one of them known as Silver Fox), joining the Canadian military, living in Japan under the name “Patch,” and fighting in World War II with Captain America.4 After returning to Canada, Logan is recruited by Team X, and as a part of the program, Wolverine has his memory erased and replaced with memories of a life that no one ever lived.5
New Wolverine!
The man involved with Team X has no memory of the life prior to being a part of the team, so we are on the second life of Wolverine.
While a member of Team X, Logan was abducted by the people at the Weapon X program. As a part of the Weapon X program, he was given the name Mutate #9601 and once again had his mind erased.
New Wolverine!
And thus ended the short life of the second Wolverine.
Not all of the life of Mutate #9601 has been documented, but we have seen some of his nasty and brutish life in Barry Windsor-Smith’s feature “Weapon X” that appeared in Marvel Comics Presents #72-84 (every comic fan should own a copy of this, as there is little better than Windsor-Smith art). Eventually, the Winter Soldier (a brainwashed Bucky) frees him, and the creature referred to as Weapon X goes feral in the woods of Canada and has his famous fight with the Hulk.6 After some time, he is discovered by James and Heather Hudson (of Alpha Flight fame), with no memory of what he was doing in the woods, the fight with the Hulk, or the Weapon X project, and in time is civilized.7
New Wolverine!
At this point, the Wolverine we all know and love is born.
I will spare you a complete rundown of the rest of Wolverine’s history (as I am sure you know it all), except to point to two other important events. When Apocalypse captures Wolverine to make him serve as his horseman Death, in Wolverine Vol. 2 #145, he was once again brainwashed.
New Wolver—okay, that’s probably enough of that.
With the conclusion of House of M, we discover that after Wolverine’s body heals from the Scarlet Witch’s messing with his mind, he finally has all of his memories restored, giving us one final new person, in Locke’s view. Wolverine now has memories or connected memories to every person who inhabited that familiar body. At this point it seems that if Locke is right, the inhabitant of the Wolverine body will in one moment go from not being responsible for any of the things done by the other inhabitants of that body to being responsible for all of them.
Jamie Madrox and Derek Parfit
The contemporary philosopher Derek Parfit (b. 1942) has famously objected to the memory account of personal identity with a thought experiment about a brain being divided into two parts and placed in two separate bodies. Had Parfit been an X-Men fan, he could have used the example of Jamie Madrox, the Multipleman. For those who don’t know, Madrox has the ability to create up to ninety-nine duplicates of himself at a time. To form a duplicate, a force must be applied to Madrox from outside himself, or he must apply the force to an outside object—in other words, he has to be hit by or hit something. At any time, two adjacent Madroxes can recombine by an act of mutual will.
When the Madroxes combine, all memories each of them had separately are joined into the new entity. Likewise, whenever a duplicate is formed, it has all of the memories of the Madrox from which it came. So, as we learn in the miniseries Madrox