Table of Contents
The Instructor's Guide
Title Page
Copyright
Preface to the Sixth Edition
Acknowledgments
The Author
Chapter One: Introduction
What Is Ethics?
Responsibility and Role
The Responsible Administrator
A Design Approach
Overview of the Contents
Conclusion
Chapter Two: Understanding Ethical Decision Making
Ethical Problems
Ethics as an Active Process
Descriptive Models of Ethical Decision Making: The World as It Is
A Prescriptive Decision-Making Model: The World as We Would Like It to Be
Conclusion
Part One: Ethics for Individual Administrators
Chapter Three: Public Administration in Modern and Postmodern Society: The Context of Administrative Ethics
Problems with Modernity in a Postmodern World
Implications for Public Administration
Political Theory and Administrative Ethics
Conclusion
Chapter Four: Administrative Responsibility: The Key to Administrative Ethics
Objective Responsibility
Subjective Responsibility
“What to Do About Mrs. Carmichael”
Conclusion
Chapter Five: Conflicts of Responsibility: The Ethical Dilemma
Conflicts of Authority
Role Conflicts
Conflicts of Interest
Maintaining the Public Trust
Conclusion
Part Two: Ethics in the Organization
Chapter Six: Maintaining Responsible Conduct in Public Organizations: Two Approaches
The Situational Context
Internal and External Controls
Conclusion
Chapter Seven: Integrating Ethics with Organizational Norms and Structures
Conflicts Among Internal and External Controls
The Components of Responsible Conduct
“Much Ado About Something” Revisited
Conclusion
Chapter Eight: Safeguarding Ethical Autonomy in Organizations: Dealing with Unethical Superiors and Organizations
Responsibility to Superiors
Sources of Organizational Pressure: The Team Player Ethic
Organizational Remedies
Individual Responsibility
Individual Ethical Autonomy in Organizations
Components of Individual Autonomy
Conclusion
Part Three: The Design Approach
Chapter Nine: Applying the Design Approach to Public Administration Ethics
The Design Approach to Public Administration Ethics
General Application
A Specific Application
Conclusion
Chapter 10: Conclusion: Responsible Administration
The Responsible Administrator
A Model of Responsible Administration
References
Index
Copyright © 2012 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc. All rights reserved.
Published by Jossey-Bass
A Wiley Imprint
One Montgomery Street, Suite 1200, San Francisco, CA 94104-4594—www.josseybass.com
No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, scanning, or otherwise, except as permitted under Section 107 or 108 of the 1976 United States Copyright Act, without either the prior written permission of the publisher, or authorization through payment of the appropriate per-copy fee to the Copyright Clearance Center, Inc., 222 Rosewood Drive, Danvers, MA 01923, 978-750-8400, fax 978-646-8600, or on the Web at www.copyright.com. Requests to the publisher for permission should be addressed to the Permissions Department, John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 111 River Street, Hoboken, NJ 07030, 201-748-6011, fax 201-748-6008, or online at www.wiley.com/go/permissions.
Limit of Liability/Disclaimer of Warranty: While the publisher and author have used their best efforts in preparing this book, they make no representations or warranties with respect to the accuracy or completeness of the contents of this book and specifically disclaim any implied warranties of merchantability or fitness for a particular purpose. No warranty may be created or extended by sales representatives or written sales materials. The advice and strategies contained herein may not be suitable for your situation. You should consult with a professional where appropriate. Neither the publisher nor author shall be liable for any loss of profit or any other commercial damages, including but not limited to special, incidental, consequential, or other damages. Readers should be aware that Internet Web sites offered as citations and/or sources for further information may have changed or disappeared between the time this was written and when it is read.
Jossey-Bass books and products are available through most bookstores. To contact Jossey-Bass directly call our Customer Care Department within the U.S. at 800-956-7739, outside the U.S. at 317-572-3986, or fax 317-572-4002.
Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats and by print-on-demand. Some material included with standard print versions of this book may not be included in e-books or in print-on-demand. If the version of this book that you purchased references media such as CD or DVD that was not included in your purchase, you may download this material at http://booksupport.wiley.com. For more information about Wiley products, visit www.wiley.com.
Cataloging-in-Publication data on file with the Library of Congress.
ISBN 978-0-470-87394-6 (hardback); ISBN 978-1-118-18052-5 (ebk); ISBN 978-1-118-18053-2 (ebk); ISBN 978-1-118-18054-9 (ebk)
Preface to the Sixth Edition
By the time this sixth edition is published, The Responsible Administrator will have been in print for thirty years. When the first edition appeared I never dreamed in my wildest fantasies that this book would have so long a life. In 1982, there was very little interest in administrative ethics among either scholars or practitioners of public administration. There was only one other book by a single author available on administrative ethics, John Rohr's Ethics for Bureaucrats, which came out in 1978 and focused on the “regime values” found in the U.S. constitutional tradition as a foundation for administrative ethics. There was also a volume of essays, edited by Joel Fleishman and others, titled Public Duties: The Moral Obligations of Government Officials, and published in 1981. There were just a few courses on this subject in academic programs and only a scattering of panels at the annual conferences of the American Society for Public Administration (ASPA) and the National Association of Schools of Public Affairs and Administration (NASPAA).
By now many more books and scholarly journal articles have appeared in print, our major professional conferences regularly have a significant cluster of panel sessions on administrative ethics, conferences specifically on ethics are conducted from time to time, and all the NASPAA-accredited MPA degree programs include a treatment of the subject. This sixth edition seeks to acknowledge the changes in the field and the advances in research while remaining true to the basic framework of the first edition. The chapters and the references have been extensively updated to reflect the recent research in the field. A new section on descriptive ethical decision-making models, which depict the way people tend to make ethical decisions, has been added. This is intended to contrast with the normative prescriptive model advanced in this book, a model developed progressively since the first edition. There is also new material on such topics as whistle-blowing, the bystander effect, and the design approach to administrative ethics.
The Responsible Administrator was written for students and practitioners of public administration who want to develop their ethical as well as technical competence. It is for men and women in public service, or preparing for it, who sometimes worry about the right thing to do, but who either have not taken the time to read books on ethical theory or suspect that such treatises would not be helpful at the practical level. It is being read by administrators and students of public administration around the world. For example, the fourth and fifth editions have been translated into Chinese, and the book is now one of the required core texts for the more than one hundred MPA programs in China.
The education, training, and day-to-day practice of public administrators tend to be dominated by the practical problems of getting the job done. Concerns about what should be done and why it should be done get swept aside by the pressures of schedule and workload. Modern society is preoccupied with action, to the exclusion of reflection about values and principles. Theory is reduced to theories that concern means—“how to” crowds out “toward what end?”
Ethical theory, in particular, tends to suffer under the sway of this mentality. Because ethics involves substantive reasoning about obligations, consequences, and ultimate ends, its immediate utility for a producing and consuming society is suspect. Principles and values, goods and oughts, seem pretty wispy stuff compared to cost-benefit ratios, GNP, tensile strength, organizational structures, assembly lines, budgets, downsizing, deadlines, outsourcing through contracts, interest group lobbying, and political pressures. The payoff for dealing formally with ethics is unclear for individual administrators and for organizations as well.
The result is a tendency either to totally ignore the study of ethics or to deal with ethics superficially.
Although it seems that the time devoted to the study of ethics in graduate courses in public administration is growing, there is still no clear consensus that every MPA curriculum should include a required, freestanding course on the subject. NASPAA has required only that ethics be treated in the MPA curriculum, and in many MPA programs accredited by NASPAA, ethics is handled as a subtopic within other core areas of the curriculum. This means that ethics generally receives fragmentary attention, with a session here and a module there in various courses. Thus it often lacks the kind of coherent and integrated treatment thought necessary for the core topics of the field, such as public finance, public policy, human resource management, and quantitative methods. Administrative ethics is still treated like a stepchild of the field. In 2009, NASPAA adopted new, competency-based accreditation guidelines that refer to “public service values” rather than ethics. It remains to be seen what effects this may have on the curricular treatment of ethics, if any. I have participated with a group from the ASPA Section on Ethics to explore the meaning of ethical competence, and I am coediting a volume with Donald Menzel on achieving ethical competency.
Among those beyond the academy, at an earlier stage there seems to have been an uneasiness with the formal study of ethics, rooted in an assumption that ethics is simply a matter of relativity and subjectivity. In a pluralistic society, where no one religious or cultural tradition is dominant, ethics has been viewed as a private, individual matter, not susceptible to the canons of rational inquiry. To address the study of ethics openly in an academic setting was thought to run the risk of either creating unresolvable conflicts among those who hold differing ethical perspectives or unfairly propagandizing for one particular point of view. However, Americans appear to have become more comfortable with the topic of ethics in public life and with the existence of academic courses on ethics and the treatment of ethics in courses on other topics.
So even though administrative ethics as a field of study has not been as fully accepted and supported as I would have liked, it is clear that the number of scholars and practitioners who are working on related topics, both in the academy and in governments at every level, in both the United States and around the world, has increased enormously since the mid 1970s. Furthermore, we have made significant progress toward establishing the importance of administrative ethics as a central concern of public administration.
Acknowledgments
Thirty years after the first edition of The Responsible Administrator was published, my intellectual honesty and humility still require admitting that writing a book is not a task for which an author ought to take sole credit. The more I write and reflect, the more I interact with students in the classroom, and the more I converse with colleagues around the world, the clearer it becomes that scholarship is truly a collective enterprise. Even books that carry the name of a single author are shaped increasingly over time by those who read them.
I am indebted to the many undergraduate students who, for more than twenty years, have taken my course “Citizenship and Public Ethics,” a required part of the core of the undergraduate program in the School of Policy, Planning, and Development at the University of Southern California. Their blunt questions and serious challenges have deepened my thinking and forced me to be clearer in expressing my views. Their interest in the subject of public ethics and the intensity of their struggles with their own professional obligations have stimulated lively debates that have caused me to rethink my own perspective. The lack of interest in ethics by some has also led me to find ways of engaging those who view the subject differently from me.
I have also learned greatly from teaching my graduate “Public Ethics” course every summer for the last fifteen years or so. That class has typically included seasoned practitioners, younger graduate students just beginning practice, and a few doctoral students developing the background to teach an ethics course and do research on the subject during their academic careers. The major paper for the course involves the analysis of a real case, either from their own experience for those with significant employment backgrounds or from the experience of someone they interview in depth for those who are early in their careers. That course is a treat that I anticipate eagerly every spring. In it I have broadened the scope of my treatment of ethics to include administrative ethics, political ethics, and policy ethics, because the people who occupy roles related to those fields interact with each other in significant ways. However, the center of gravity resides with administrative ethics.
I express my deepest appreciation to the women and men at all levels of American public service who have shared their struggles, insights, and creativity with me. Their cases and the ensuing discussions in ethics workshops I have conducted since 1975 are the empirical basis for this book and a major source of any knowledge I may be able to pass along. I have been deeply impressed by their intention to do the right thing in the face of formidable impediments. I hold their contributions to ethics in public administration in respectful trust and pass this knowledge along as their gift to me and the reader.
I thank my colleagues around the world who are teaching and engaging in research on administrative ethics. Our numbers have grown substantially since 1982 when The Responsible Administrator first appeared. Through sessions at the annual conferences of ASPA and at other smaller meetings in the United States, Canada, Hong Kong, France, China, and Australia, I have observed that a genuine community of scholars and practitioners is emerging worldwide that is committed to the development of public administrative ethics.
My thanks also go to the reviewers, who once again carefully examined the previous edition of this book and gave me their constructive advice, and to Allison Brunner and Alison Hankey at Jossey-Bass, whose excellent editorial guidance and patience have been invaluable.
I express again my continuing gratitude to my dearest and best colleague, my wife, Megan, whose inspiration, insights, writing skill, knowledge of the field of public administration, and personal support have been freely and warmly given since the first edition and again at every stage of this project. She helped me shape The Responsible Administrator from the very beginning with her advice and suggestions as I began outlining the book in a mountain cabin in Southern California in the late 1970s, and her assistance and support continued throughout the writing process.
I must again also acknowledge the moral guide in my life, who has become more collegial since the previous edition, my daughter, Chelsea. Throughout her twenty-six years of life, she has caused me to take my own ethics more seriously. Her honest and direct questions have called me up short and caused me to reflect. Her “Why?” questions and her observations about the gap between what I say and what I do have deepened my moral life. This book has made its way through five previous editions as she has grown up and taken her own place in the practice of international maternal and child health. Observing her moral development from infancy to young adulthood has illuminated my understanding of how we humans are most fundamentally valuing creatures. I have watched her expressing her own values and deep commitments in her work in places like Uganda, South Sudan, Rwanda, Kenya, Liberia, Tanzania, South Africa, Afghanistan, Thailand, and India and been reminded that I still have much to learn from her.
Finally, I express my deep appreciation to Bryce Lowery, whose creativity, hard work, research skills, editorial competence, excellent writing, and endless patience have been absolutely essential in getting this sixth edition to the press. Bryce is completing his PhD dissertation and has previously worked with me as a teaching assistant in my undergraduate “Citizenship and Public Ethics” class. He is on his way to a distinguished career as a scholar and teacher in the field of urban planning for the outstanding university lucky enough to hire him. He will leave us someday soon also fully prepared to teach ethics along with his major field.
All of these people and many others have helped to broaden, deepen, and sharpen my thoughts. I deeply appreciate their gifts to me and hope that what I have done with them in these pages is worthy of their respect.
Los Angeles, California
Terry L. Cooper
June 2011
Chapter One
Introduction
The Responsible Administrator is one attempt to respond to the need for a systematic treatment of public administrative ethics that is grounded in both the realities of practice and the requirements of sound scholarship. It is important to identify the particular contribution intended here. The conceptual focus of the book is the role of the public administrator in an organizational setting; the central integrating ethical concept used in dealing with that role is responsibility. The central ethical process adopted for addressing ethical problems associated with administrative responsibility is a comprehensive design approach.
What Is Ethics?
Ethics is defined in various ways, some more technical and precise than others. The usual brief textbook or dictionary definitions define ethics as “the attempt to state and evaluate principles by which ethical problems may be solved” (Jones, Sontag, Becker, and Fogelin, 1969, p. 1), “the normative standards of conduct derived from the philosophical and religious traditions of society” (Means, 1970, p. 52), or “the task of careful reflection several steps removed from the actual conduct of men” concerning “the assumptions and presuppositions of the moral life” (Gustafson, 1965, p. 113). Preston (1996) becomes a bit more specific by suggesting that “ethics is concerned about what is right, fair, just, or good; about what we ought to do, not just about what is the case or what is most acceptable or expedient” (p. 16). M. W. Martin (1995) defines ethics as moral philosophy and stipulates that it includes four main goals or interests: clarification of moral concepts; critical evaluation of moral claims focused on “testing their truth, justification, and adequacy” (pp. 7–8); constructing an inclusive perspective by elucidating the interconnections among moral ideas and values; and providing moral guidance through improving practical judgment.
Gibson Winter (1966) defines ethics more comprehensively by describing the functions it serves in the social world. As an active enterprise, he says, “Ethics seeks to clarify the logic and adequacy of the values that shape the world; it assesses the moral possibilities which are projected and betrayed in the social give-and-take” (p. 218). Anyone engaged in ethical reflection takes on the task of analyzing and evaluating the principles embodied in various alternatives for conduct and social order. Ethics is, according to Winter, “a science of human intentionality” (p. 219).
For our purposes in this book, ethics may be understood as the study of moral conduct and moral status. Ethics and morality are often used interchangeably, but here I will distinguish them. Morality assumes some accepted modes of behavior that are given by a religious tradition, a culture (including an organizational culture), a social class, a community, or a family. It involves expected courses of conduct that are rooted in both formal rules and informal norms. Morality is expressed through such precepts as “decent young people do not engage in premarital sex,” “family comes first,” “one should not conspicuously display one's wealth,” “guests in one's home must always be treated with respect,” “never drive under the influence,” “a day's pay requires a day's work,” “follow the orders of those above you in the organization,” and similar expectations. Sometimes these expectations are written out in codes of conduct or rules, but at other times they are assumed and taken for granted. Typically they are asserted by a tradition, culture, religion, community, organization, or family as simply what is right.
Ethics, then, is one step removed from action. It involves the examination and analysis of the logic, values, beliefs, and principles that are used to justify morality in its various forms. It considers what is meant by principles such as justice, veracity, or the public interest; their implications for conduct in particular situations; and how one might argue for one principle over another as determinative in a particular decision. Ethics takes what is given or prescribed and asks what is meant and why. So ethics as related to conduct is critical reflection on morality toward grounding moral conduct in systematic reflection and reasoning. Ethical reflection also involves an affective element because it often evokes emotive responses of comfort or discomfort, resolution or quandary, and affirmation or antagonism.
Ethics also deals with the moral status of entities such as families, organizations, communities, and societies. Here ethical reasoning is focused on how the characteristics associated with the good family, the good organization, or the good society are grounded in certain principles, values, beliefs, and logical argument. Ethics weighs the adequacy of these attributes and analyzes how they are justified.
Ethics may be dealt with descriptively or normatively. Descriptively, ethics attempts to reveal underlying assumptions and how they are connected to conduct. Normatively, ethics attempts to construct viable and defensible arguments for particular courses of conduct as being better than others in specific situations. This book engages mainly in a descriptive approach to the ethical situation of public administrators and provides some analytical tools, including a decision model for arriving at normative judgments. It does not describe a particular public service ethic, an endeavor I have undertaken in another book, An Ethic of Citizenship for Public Administration (1991), nor does it specifically define a descriptive decision model. Descriptive models developed by others will be reviewed briefly in Chapter Two as a means of providing background for the normative model presented here.
Ethics may be viewed from either or both of two major orientations: deontological and teleological. Deontological approaches to ethics focus on one's duty to certain ethical principles, such as justice, freedom, or veracity, without regard for the consequences of one's actions. Teleological ethics, in contrast, involves a concern for the ends or consequences of one's conduct. This is the position most notably associated with utilitarianism and its calculus of the greatest good for the greatest number. This book assumes that most of us undertake decisions using both of these perspectives most of the time. That is, we consider principles that are important to us in a concrete situation and then ask ourselves what the consequences of acting on those principles are likely to be. The decision-making model presented in the next chapter combines deontological and teleological orientations.
Doing ethics, then, involves thinking more systematically about the values and principles that are embedded in our choices than we do when we make choices on practical or political grounds alone. As we reflect on these implicit values, we ask ourselves how they are consistent with our duties and toward what ends and consequences they lead. Keeping in mind the obligations and goals of the roles we occupy, we seek to rank-order them for each particular ethical decision we confront in the course of carrying out a specific role.
The relationship between law and ethics often comes up in the discussion of specific cases. My answer is that law specifies the moral minimum. It is the minimum level of conduct that we as a society agree to impose on all of us through the threat of force and sanctions. Ethical considerations are often involved in deliberations about proposed legislation, but once crystallized into law, the conduct prescribed is assumed to be backed up by the coercive power of government. However, from an ethicist's point of view, law must always stand under the judgment of ethics. Sometimes laws may be deemed unjust and therefore unethical. Those who believe so may challenge those laws in the courts as inconsistent with the human rights guaranteed by the U.S. Constitution, or they may engage in civil disobedience, even to the point of being arrested and going to jail.
Both kinds of challenges occurred during the civil rights movement of the 1960s and 1970s. The National Association for the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP) engaged in litigation against unjust segregation laws in the American South. Martin Luther King Jr. and many others employed civil disobedience by sitting in at segregated facilities, refusing to sit in the back seats on buses, and demonstrating against segregated schools even when ordered by legal authorities not to do so. Sometimes laws need to be challenged on ethical grounds. In the long tradition of civil disobedience exemplified by Gandhi and King, the key proviso is that one must be willing to accept the consequences of one's actions in order to demonstrate commitment to ethical principles over what are considered unjust laws. That is, one must be willing to suffer fines and imprisonment in order to evoke a response from the larger society to bring about change in the laws in question.
Responsibility and Role
The terms role and responsibility are peculiarly modern in connotation. Both suggest a worldview in which the power of tradition is broken and human beings are left to construct a world of their own making. Roles must be devised and responsibility defined as ways of reestablishing obligations in our modern, pluralistic, technological society. Technology is applied not only to production but also to society itself.
Winter (1966) observed: “Responsibility is a relatively new term in the ethical vocabulary, appearing in the nineteenth century with a somewhat ambiguous meaning. The term evaluates action and attributes it to an agent; it does so in lieu of cosmic or natural structures of obligation. The historical awareness of the nineteenth century, the scientific and technological revolutions, and the collapse of metaphysical systems had undermined fixed notions of obligations. The term ‘responsibility’ was a way of filling this gap by defining the scope of accountability and obligation in contexts of law and common culture” (pp. 254–255).
Similarly, Richard McKeon's study (1957) of the emergence of the term in Western thought reveals that responsibility first appeared in English and French in 1787. It was used initially in reference to the political institutions arising out of the American and French revolutions, but its use continued through the nineteenth century. When “constitutional government was vastly extended, in scope of operation and in spread among nations, as a result of contacts of cultures and peoples” (p. 23), the concept of responsibility became increasingly significant as a way of defining a common set of values among people of divergent cultures and traditions.
The concept of role then becomes a convenient way to package expectations and obligations associated with the modern world. As we cease to view social functions as received intact from the past and see them instead as manipulated and created anew, we take upon ourselves bounded obligation in the form of various roles. People exercise responsibility and are held responsible in society when they accept and carry out an array of more or less well-defined roles: employee, parent, citizen, group member. The most problematic roles are those not clearly defined, usually because there is little agreement about the boundaries of responsibility associated with them. What does it mean to be a responsible parent in the first decade of the twenty-first century? Or a responsible spouse, responsible citizen, responsible politician, or responsible public administrator?
The problem is that although public administrators are responsible for certain duties (those that constitute the professional role), they sometimes believe they are obligated to act otherwise. This occurs because administrators, along with everyone else in modern society, maintain an array of roles related to family, community, and society, each carrying a set of obligations and vested with certain personal interests. The quite common result is conflict among roles as these competing forces push and pull in opposite directions. The effects of these conflicts are compounded by the range of discretion administrators must exercise. The intent of legislation is frequently stated in broad language, leaving the specifics to administrators. Consequently, ethical standards and sensitivity are crucial to the responsible use of this discretion.
The Responsible Administrator
The responsible administrator is one who is responsible in the two senses I have discussed briefly here (this subject is treated more thoroughly in Chapter Four). Responsible administrators must be able to account for their conduct to relevant others, such as supervisors, elected officials, the courts, and the citizenry, which means being able to explain and justify why specific actions they took resulted in particular consequences. They must also be able to act in ways that are consistent with their inner convictions as professional guardians of the public good. That is, being a responsible administrator includes having both objective accountability for conduct and subjective congruence with one's professional values. Ethics is the most fundamental way in which one satisfies both kinds of responsibility. Responsible administrators must be ethically sophisticated enough to reason with others about the ways in which their conduct serves the public interest and have sufficient clarity about their own professional ethical commitments to maintain integrity and a sense of self-esteem.
What, then, is the difference between an ethical administrator and a responsible administrator? A public administrator who has been properly socialized may be able to act in accordance with the common good some or even most of the time, thus being an ethical administrator some or most of the time, yet not be able to give specific reasons for his or her conduct when questioned or challenged, and perhaps not even be able to understand in a self-conscious way why he or she acted in a particular way. Understanding one's motivations and being able to explain and justify the actions that flow from them are the essential qualities of the responsible administrator. This book seeks to provide the concepts, theories, and techniques for responsible administration.
A Design Approach
All too many treatments of professional ethics stop with a conceptual and theoretical philosophical analysis of typical ethical problems. Some lead to a desired solution or a prescribed set of ethical norms, whereas others elucidate the problem, offer some analysis of various alternatives, and leave the reader with the implication that all are of equal value. In this book a design approach is adopted as the central organizing ethical process. This orientation assumes that there is no single best solution to a significant ethical problem but rather numerous possible solutions, some of equal value and some of greater or lesser worth. The task is to design a response to a problem at hand that addresses the immediate short-term situation but also looks to the wider organizational, legal, and social contexts for the longer-term answers.
Practicing administrators cannot live exclusively in the realm of philosophical reflection but must connect such considerations to action and organizations. As Caroline Whitbeck (1996) suggests, “People confronted with ethical problems must do more than simply make judgments. They must figure out what to do” (p. 9). Far from simply assuming that ethics is a matter of looking for an ideal rational solution to an immediate problem, Whitbeck argues that a person confronting an ethical problem should be thinking like a designer. “Design problems,” she points out, “are problems of making (or repairing) things and processes to satisfy wants and needs” (p. 10). And this “making” and “repairing” always involves constraints—in time, money, power, the ability to persuade, and the strength to absorb consequences. For public administrators the design of a viable and acceptable solution to an ethical quandary always takes place in the context of organizations that will support some kinds of conduct and impede others. A workable resolution of an ethical problem cannot ignore that organizational context.
Following Whitbeck, the approach developed throughout this book is one of considering the facts of a situation—its social and organizational context, its constraints, opportunities, and implications for all concerned—and then advocating the design of courses of action that may include changes in organizational structure, culture, rules, policies, and procedures. It is assumed that there are several conceivable alternative courses to consider before selecting, not an ideal or perfect solution, but the best among an array of possibilities, some of which may be equally acceptable. This design approach assumes that it is always possible to improve on any solution given moral imagination, ingenuity, and creativity and that one must always bring these qualities to bear on important ethical quandaries. But administrators have limited time to exercise their inventiveness and finally must act in the short run while planning for the future.
Thus, as the chapters unfold, the meaning of responsibility in the public administrative role will be developed by leading the reader through considerations of the elements involved in designing what to do in the face of ethical uncertainty and challenge. Here are some lessons that Whitbeck has advanced for designing responses to moral problems:
- We should begin with a consideration of the uncertainties involved in any ethical problem. For example, no one should ever assume that appearances are always true. Conduct that may seem to be unethical may not be when it is fully explored and understood. Also, human behavior is not always predictable. A person may decide on a course of action and then find out that the key actors respond very differently from what had been expected. As the process of addressing a problem unfolds, the nature of the problem may change. Other issues and conflicts heretofore unknown may be discovered to be involved in the problem.
- The generation of alternative solutions to an ethical problem is separate from defining the problem and may necessitate gathering additional information. This is related to the previous lesson. In order to reduce uncertainty, it is often necessary to find out more about who is involved in the problem, how long it has existed, the characters of the key actors, the implications of various options for action for the larger organization and people within it, and how key actors outside the organization may respond to the proposed courses of action.
- We are always acting under time pressure. Busy public administrators do not have the luxury of contemplating an ethical problem until they are fully satisfied that all options and contingencies have been exhaustively considered. Decisions have to be made and things have to get done, always under constraints of schedules and deadlines. Sometimes that means pursuing several alternatives simultaneously or developing a contingency approach, with a decision tree indicating what will be done if various things do not happen as initially planned. Not taking this approach may mean that the opportunity to intervene and correct misconduct may be lost. Postponing action may result in a fait accompli. The damage may be done, and irreversibly so.
- Ethical problems are dynamic. They change as we begin to address them. What we may at first engage as an ethical problem may become also a legal problem. Or while we are beginning to work through a planned course of action to address an ethical problem, someone else may intervene and resolve it in another way, which may in turn create an entirely new problem.
These lessons are rather abstract at this point, but readers should try to keep them in mind as the chapters unfold. (Chapter Nine develops this design approach in summary fashion by applying it to a case.)
Overview of the Contents
The first and most basic task of this book is to illuminate the ethical decision-making process. Chapter Two begins with some basic concepts for understanding the levels of deliberation at which ethical problems are addressed. This is followed by a model for analyzing and resolving these problems. The model is partly linear, involving a sequence of steps, and partly nonlinear, requiring a search for the integration of several key elements, including moral rules, ethical principles, self-image, and the norms of the political community. It also combines reasoning, emotions, and beliefs. The model presented here is not simply rationalist and focused on principles but also includes, as essential, the affective dimensions of ethical decision making and conduct. The logic espoused is not a linear syllogistic calculus but something more like the logic of aesthetics or the logic of rhetoric. Some readers seem to have missed this essential thrust in earlier editions of the book (Bruce, 1992; Cooper, 1992a; Cooper, 1996; Harmon, 1995). This chapter concludes with a summary of the design approach that is developed through the remaining chapters.
Chapter Three develops the social context within which the public administrator must work and discusses the problem of defining and maintaining the administrator's role in the diverse and relativistic environment of modern society. Without the guidance of a coherent tradition, the administrative role in modern societies is just one more set of obligations and interests that must be managed amid an array of other competing roles. One significant outcome of this social context is the inescapably political nature of public administration today.
Chapter Four addresses the dual nature of administrative responsibility in modern society: administrators have both objective responsibility (in which one is held accountable by superiors, the public, and legislation) and subjective responsibility (in which one feels and believes oneself to be responsible). Conflict between these two forms of responsibility seems to be the most common form in which ethical dilemmas emerge.
Chapter Five further develops the conflict between subjective and objective responsibility. Conflicts of authority, role, and interest are reviewed. It is not that these three forms of conflicting responsibility require distinctly different forms of analysis to be resolved. Rather, understanding the different ways we experience conflicts helps us clarify the key actors and relationships that must be examined and dealt with if we are to achieve resolution.
Chapter Six presents two general approaches to maintaining, from a management perspective, responsible conduct in public organizations—internal controls and external controls. External controls include instruments imposed on the individual from outside, such as codes of ethics and ethics legislation; internal controls involve the professional values and standards that public servants have internalized through the socialization process, both personal and professional.
Continuing the management perspective from Chapter Six, Chapter Seven focuses on the importance of establishing congruence among the various internal and external controls. Two examples illustrate what happens when this is not done. Four components of responsible conduct are then discussed: individual attributes, organizational structure, organizational culture, and societal expectations.
Chapter Eight shifts the perspective to an individual who is attempting to act ethically in the face of management that has become corrupt or lost sight of its mandated mission in the public interest. The problem is one of conflicting loyalties—to superiors on the one hand and to the public on the other. Whistle-blowing is recognized as one response to this kind of conflict. Sources of organizational pressure on individual employees are outlined, organizational remedies are discussed, and the ultimate necessity for individual responsibility is asserted. The chapter closes with a treatment of the components required for individual ethical autonomy.
It is important to note at the outset that ethical autonomy is not tantamount to ethical individualism but must be seen in the context of the previous chapters and the concluding model. Individual ethical autonomy is necessary to some degree to provide for the exercise of conscience in resistance to corrupt authority, but this exercise of conscience will always occur for public administrators in organizational, institutional, and societal contexts. The administrator is not in his or her job simply for self-fulfillment but to serve the citizenry by enhancing the public good. The public administrator is a fiduciary of the citizens, holding their common good in trust. Thus it is assumed here that women and men entering public service must be prepared to find fulfillment in this pursuit.
In Chapter Nine, I elaborate the design approach and its relevance to significant ethical problems. I restate the approach in terms appropriate for the public administrative role, using cases as examples of how the approach would be applied. I conclude the chapter by applying the design approach to a concrete case about contracting for government services.
Chapter Ten, the final chapter, summarizes the argument developed throughout the previous chapters and presents a model of responsible administration that brings together the components of responsible conduct from Chapter Seven and the components of individual ethical autonomy from Chapter Eight. Illustrative material has been added to this chapter to clarify the practical implications of the model.
The cases in the book are based on real occurrences and fictionalized only slightly to protect the privacy of those who provided them. In a few instances they are composites of several actual cases. They are intended primarily as illustrations but should also stimulate readers' thinking about the ethical problems they portray. For both these reasons the situations are left unresolved. To indicate an outcome would diminish the experience of dilemma they are calculated to evoke; it would also short-circuit the reader's own reflections. For the same reason, the case narratives are a bit longer and more detailed than usual. Again, the ultimate purpose of The Responsible Administrator is to illuminate the ethical situation of the public administrator and cultivate imaginative reflection about it—not to prescribe a particular set of public service values. This is not to suggest that all alternatives are of equal value but that the focus of this book is not on prescribing particular courses of action.
Conclusion
This book is largely descriptive and analytical; it is only secondarily prescriptive, and even then only in a particular sense. It prescribes a design approach to public administrative ethics that includes techniques individual administrators can use in analyzing ethical dilemmas they confront, and a combination of organizational and management components for fostering responsible administration.
I do not attempt to develop a substantive ethic for public administrators in this book. That is a necessary and important undertaking, but it is dealt with in another of my books, An Ethic of Citizenship for Public Administration (1991). There I develop the argument that a normative ethic for public administration is to be found in the ethical tradition of citizenship as it has evolved throughout U.S. history. This tradition has at its core the ideas of the common good, the importance of democratic participation by the citizenry, and the ultimate sovereignty of the people. The public administrator is viewed there as taking his or her ethical norms from those of citizenship in a democratic society. The administrator is a fiduciary professional citizen in some sense. For the purposes of this book, some such public service ethic is assumed.