Contents
Notes on Contributors
Acknowledgments
General Introduction
Who Is This Book for?
What Is Bioethics?
The Canon of Bioethics
Motivations for Topics in Bioethics
The Classification of Bioethics
A Philosophical Discipline
Dealing with Hot-Button Issues
References
Part 1 Are There Universal Ethical Principles That Should Govern the Conduct of Medicine and Research Worldwide?
Introduction
References
Chapter One There Are Universal Ethical Principles That Should Govern the Conduct of Medicine and Research Worldwide
Introduction
The Universalism–Particularism Debate in Historical Perspective
Emergence of the Concept of Human Dignity
The Dynamics of Dignity and Moral Particularism
Conclusion
References
Chapter Two There Are No Universal Ethical Principles That Should Govern the Conduct of Medicine and Research Worldwide
Introduction
Principles: One Part of a Balanced Breakfast
Universalism: Promises and Pitfalls
Binding Moral Norms and Self-Evidence
Conclusion
References
Reply to Decker
References
Reply to Pullman
Human Dignity and Speciesism
The Redundancy of Basic Dignity
Conclusion
References
Part 2 Is It Morally Acceptable to Buy and Sell Organs for Human Transplantation?
Introduction
References
Chapter Three It Is Morally Acceptable to Buy and Sell Organs for Human Transplantation
Introduction
Some Background Numbers
Financial Incentives: Increasing Access to Transplantation
Human Organs Are Instrumental Goods
Marketplace Morality
Coerced Altruism
Persons and Their Bodies
Conclusion
Acknowledgment
References
Chapter Four It Is Not Morally Acceptable to Buy and Sell Organs for Human Transplantation
The Harsh Reality of Allowing Markets in Organs—Trafficking of the Poor
Scarcity—Bad, Underestimated, and Growing Worse
Duties to Those in Need and Duties to Those Who Might Supply an Organ
The Prevailing Ethical Framework for Obtaining Organs and Tissues
Increasing the Supply
The Trouble with Markets in Kidneys
A Better Option—Default to Donation
Conclusion
References
Reply to Caplan
References
Reply to Cherry
Part 3 Were It Physically Safe, Would Human Reproductive Cloning Be Acceptable?
Introduction
References
Chapter Five Were It Physically Safe, Human Reproductive Cloning Would Be Acceptable
Dolly: A Wolf in Sheep’s Clothing?
What Is Reproductive Cloning?
The Argument that Reproductive Cloning Is Physically Unsafe
Reasons For Reproductive Cloning
Reasons Against Reproductive Cloning
Harm to Others
Eugenics
Human Dignity
Conclusion
Note
References
Chapter Six Were It Physically Safe, Human Reproductive Cloning Would Not Be Acceptable
Introduction
The Identical Twin Analogue
The ART Analogue
The Adopted Child Analogue
The Parent–Child Resemblance Analogue
The Replacement Child Analogue
Cloning as “Unnatural”
HRC as a Means
Autonomy and Beyond
Societal Prejudice and Respect
Conclusion
References
Reply to Levick
The Identical Twin Analogy
The Assisted Reproduction Analogy
The Adoption Analogy
The Parent–Child Resemblance Analogy
The Replacement Child Analogy
Reply to Devolder
On Reasoning by Analogy
The Identical Twin Analogue
The Assisted Reproductive Technology Analogue
The Parent–Child Resemblance Analogue
The Replacement Child Analogue
Devolder’s Conclusions in Her Reply
The Child of the Famous Analogue
Conclusion
References
Part 4 Is the Deliberately Induced Abortion of a Human Pregnancy Ethically Justifiable?
Introduction
References
Chapter Seven The Deliberately Induced Abortion of a Human Pregnancy Is Ethically Justifiable
Introduction
The Moral Question of Abortion: Learning about the Key from the Keyhole
The Asymmetric Value of Human Life: Respecting Persons and Protecting Their Lives
Morality and Mattering: What Makes Killing Humans Wrong
References
Chapter Eight The Deliberately Induced Abortion of a Human Pregnancy Is Not Ethically Justifiable
The Reproductive Freedom Perspective
The Innocent-Human-Life Perspective
Warren’s Personhood Perspective
The Pro-Attitude Perspective
The Future of Value View
The P-Future of Value View
The Superiority of the P-Future of Value View
The Ideal Desire Perspective
Thomson’s Defense of Abortion Rights
Conclusion
References
Reply to Marquis
Reply to Reiman
References
Part 5 Is It Ethical to Patent or Copyright Genes, Embryos, or Their Parts?
Introduction
References
Chapter Nine It Is Ethical to Patent or Copyright Genes, Embryos, or Their Parts
Introduction
Intellectual Property Rights
Creativity and Innovation Policy
Ethics and Morality
Myths and Legends
Genes, Embryos, and Their Parts
Patent Eligible Subject Matter
A Path Forward?
Notes
References
Chapter Ten It Is Not Ethical to Patent or Copyright Genes, Embryos, or Their Parts
Introduction
Intellectual Property
Patenting “Life”
Consequentialism
Deontological Arguments
Conclusions
References
Reply to Koepsell
Reply to Sung
References
Part 6 Should a Child Have the Right to Refuse Medical Treatment to Which the Child’s Parents or Guardians Have Consented?
Introduction
References
Chapter Eleven The Child Should Have the Right to Refuse Medical Treatment to Which the Child’s Parents or Guardians Have Consented
Introduction
Competence and Incompetence
Legal Incompetence of Minors and the Categorical Age Criterion
The Moral Rights of Adolescents to Consent to or Refuse Medical Treatment
Treatment-Refusal Situations
References
Chapter Twelve The Child Should Not Have the Right to Refuse Medical Treatment to Which the Child’s Parents or Guardians Have Consented
Introduction
Speaking the Language of Rights in the Vernacular of the Law
A Foundation in Law: The Child and the Parent
The Law, Psychology, and Neurology: Consent and Refusal to Consent, or Dissent
The Right to Decide: Consent and the Refusal of Consent
Conclusion: Respecting Childhood and Adolescence
Note
References
Reply to Brooks
Reply to Winslade
Part 7 Is Physician-Assisted Suicide Ever Ethical?
Introduction
References
Chapter Thirteen Physician-Assisted Suicide Is Ethical
Introduction
Magda
The Value of Human Life
Confusing Essence with Existence
Social and Political Reasons
Kant and Mill
The Morality of Suicide and Physician-Assisted Suicide
Being Careful, Cautious, and Conscientious
Provisos
References
Chapter Fourteen Physician-Assisted Suicide Is Not Ethical
Introduction
Why Intentionally Killing Innocent People (Including Oneself) Is Morally Wrong
Intentional Killing vs. Accepting Death as a Side Effect
The Denial That Life Is in Itself Valuable
Can Innocent Human Life Lose Its Value?
Can the Intrinsic Value of Life Be Outweighed by Other Considerations?
References
Reply to Lee
Objective Values
Human Nature
Shaping Lives
Life as a Basic Good
Benefits and Burdens
Losing Features
Reply to Lachs
Part 8 Should Stem-Cell Research Utilizing Embryonic Tissue Be Conducted?
Introduction
References
Chapter Fifteen Stem-Cell Research Utilizing Embryonic Tissue Should Be Conducted
Introduction
What Are Stem Cells?
What Are Embryonic Stem Cells?
Embryonic Stem-Cell Research
Mistakes of Opponents
We Should Allow Stem-Cell Research
References
Chapter Sixteen Stem-Cell Research Utilizing Embryonic Tissue Should Not Be Conducted
Introduction
Respect for the Individual
Are Embryos Persons?
Arbitrary Lines
Two Responses
Warren, Singer, and Tooley
The Nothing-Is-Lost Principle and the Principle of Waste Avoidance
Conclusion: Adult Stem Cells
Note
References
Joint Reply
Part 9 Should We Prohibit the Use of Chimpanzees and Other Great Apes in Biomedical Research?
Introduction
References
Chapter Seventeen We Should Prohibit the Use of Chimpanzees and Other Great Apes in Biomedical Research
Models for Humans
Apes, Art, Trees
The Moral Status of Animals
Our Obligations to Animals
Rights for Apes
The Great Apes Are Special
Progress?
References
Chapter Eighteen We Should Not Prohibit the Use of Chimpanzees and Other Great Apes in Biomedical Research
Introduction
Biological Similarities
Chimpanzee as the Ideal Model
A Bit of History
AIDS and Hepatitis
The Continued Need for Chimpanzee Research
A Special Moral Category?
References
Reply to Cohen
References
Reply to Kazez
References
Part 10 Should the United States of America Adopt Universal Healthcare?
Introduction
References
Chapter Nineteen The United States of America Should Adopt Universal Healthcare
Introduction
Historical and International Perspectives
The Current Untenable Healthcare Landscape
The Case for UHC
The Market
Social Basis for UHC
Political Basis for UHC
UHC: A Real Alternative
Conclusion
References
Chapter Twenty The United States of America Should Not Adopt Universal Healthcare
Introduction
The “Right” to Healthcare vs. Freedom of Choice
What Is Wrong with US Healthcare?
The True Story of US Healthcare
What about Single-Payer?
Everybody’s Business: Socialized Costs vs. Personal Freedom
The Alternative
References
Reply to Whitman
References
Reply to Geyman
Mischaracterization of the US System
Hostility to Markets
Misplaced Concern with Inequality
Rose-Colored Single-Payer Glasses
References
Part 11 Is There a Legitimate Place for Human Genetic Enhancement?
Introduction
References
Chapter Twenty One There Is a Legitimate Place for Human Genetic Enhancement
Introduction
Defining Genetic Enhancement
The Interactionist View of Human Development
Potential Problems
Exploring Enhancement’s Moral Limits
The Inhumanity of Radical Enhancement
Comparing Moderate and Radical Enhancement
References
Chapter Twenty Two There Is No Legitimate Place for Human Genetic Enhancement
Introduction
The Philosophers
American Eugenics
The Final Solution
Since World War II
References
Reply to Black
Too Many Slippery Slopes
Genetic Enhancement vs. Eugenics
Slippery Slopes and Slip-Proof Ladders
References
Reply to Agar
References
Part 12 Can There Be Agreement as to What Constitutes Human Death?
Introduction
References
Chapter Twenty Three There Can Be Agreement as to What Constitutes Human Death
Statement of the Problem
A Biophilosophical Analysis of Death
The Paradigm of Death
Challenges to the Paradigm of Death
The Definition of Death
The Criterion of Death
Conclusion
Notes
References
Chapter Twenty Four There Cannot Be Agreement as to What Constitutes Human Death
Introduction
Three Examples of Death
Definitions, Criteria, and Biological Kinds
Life and Death as Biological Natural Kinds
Note
References
Reply to Chiong
References
Reply to Bernat
References
Part 13 Is There Ever a Circumstance in Which a Doctor May Withhold Information?
Introduction
References
Chapter Twenty Five There Are Circumstances in Which a Doctor May Withhold Information
Introduction
Historical Background of the Problem
A Framework of Principles for Biomedical Ethics
Problems of Autonomy Limitation: The Harm Principle and Medical Paternalism
The Nature of Autonomy-Limiting Principles
The Harm Principle and Its Import for Withholding Information from Patients
The Principle of Paternalism and Its Import for Withholding Information from Patients
Clinical Judgment and Strategies of Information Disclosure
References
Chapter Twenty Six There Are No Circumstances in Which a Doctor May Withhold Information
Introduction
History and Definition of Therapeutic Privilege
Ethical Frameworks for Analysis
Reasons Supporting Therapeutic Deception
Reasons Against Therapeutic Deception
AMA Policy
Conclusion
References
Reply to Eberl
Reply to Beauchamp
Part 14 Should In Vitro Fertilization Be an Option for a Woman?
Introduction
References
Chapter Twenty Seven In Vitro Fertilization Should Be an Option for a Woman
Introduction
Critiques of IVF
Addressing Consequentialist Concerns
No IVF!
Conclusion
References
Chapter Twenty Eight In Vitro Fertilization Should Not Be an Option for a Woman
I
II
III
IV
V
VI
VII
References
Reply to Tollefsen
Reply to Purdy
References
Part 15 Are International Clinical Trials Exploitative?
Introduction
References
Chapter Twenty Nine Clinical Trials Are Inherently Exploitative
Introduction
Exploitation and Valdman’s Position
The Motivation for International Clinical Trials
Problems with Obtaining Informed Consent in Developing Countries
The Weakness of Human Moral Motivation and Interpretation
The Argument
Conclusions
References
Chapter Thirty International Clinical Trials Are Not Inherently Exploitative
Introduction
Three Puzzles
Act Consequentialism and Priority
Multi-Level Consequentialism
Exploitation
Exploitation and the Three Puzzles
Summary
References
Reply to Arneson
References
Reply to Watson
Index
In teaching and research, philosophy makes progress through argumentation and debate. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy provides a forum for students and their teachers to follow and participate in the debates that animate philosophy today in the western world. Each volume presents pairs of opposing viewpoints on contested themes and topics in the central subfields of philosophy. Each volume is edited and introduced by an expert in the field, and also includes an index, bibliography, and suggestions for further reading. The opposing essays, commissioned especially for the volumes in the series, are thorough but accessible presentations of opposing points of view.
1. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion
edited by Michael L. Peterson and Raymond J. Vanarragon
2. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science
edited by Christopher Hitchcock
3. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology
edited by Matthias Steup and Ernest Sosa
4. Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics
edited by Andrew I. Cohen and Christopher Heath Wellman
5. Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art
edited by Matthew Kieran
6. Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory
edited by James Dreier
7. Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science
edited by Robert Stainton
8. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind
edited by Brian McLaughlin and Jonathan Cohen
9. Contemporary Debates in Social Philosophy
edited by Laurence Thomas
10. Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics
edited by Theodore Sider, John Hawthorne, and Dean W. Zimmerman
11. Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy
edited by Thomas Christiano and John Christman
12. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology
edited by Francisco J. Ayala and Robert Arp
13. Contemporary Debates in Bioethics
edited by Arthur L. Caplan and Robert Arp
This edition first published 2014
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
Wiley-Blackwell is an imprint of John Wiley & Sons, formed by the merger of Wiley’s global Scientific, Technical and Medical business with Blackwell Publishing.
Registered Office
John Wiley & Sons Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK
Editorial Offices
350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148-5020, USA
9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK
The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK
For details of our global editorial offices, for customer services, and for information about how to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at www.wiley.com/wiley-blackwell.
The right of Arthur L. Caplan and Robert Arp to be identified as the authors of the editorial material in this work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher.
Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books.
Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks. All brand names and product names used in this book are trade names, service marks, trademarks or registered trademarks of their respective owners. The publisher is not associated with any product or vendor mentioned in this book. This publication is designed to provide accurate and authoritative information in regard to the subject matter covered. It is sold on the understanding that the publisher is not engaged in rendering professional services. If professional advice or other expert assistance is required, the services of a competent professional should be sought.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Contemporary debates in bioethics / edited by Arthur L. Caplan, Robert Arp.
p. ; cm. – (Contemporary debates in philosophy ; 13)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-1-118-32847-7 (epub) – ISBN 978-1-118-32848-4 (epdf) – ISBN 978-1-118-32849-1 (emobi) – ISBN 978-1-118-32850-7 – ISBN 978-1-118-32851-4 – ISBN 978-1-4443-3713-6 (cloth : alk. paper) – ISBN 978-1-4443-3714-3 (pbk. : alk. paper)
I. Caplan, Arthur L. II. Arp, Robert. III. Series: Contemporary debates in philosophy ; 13.
[DNLM: 1. Bioethical Issues. 2. Biomedical Research–ethics. 3. Genetic Enhancement–ethics. 4. Patient Rights–ethics. 5. Reproductive Techniques–ethics. WB 60]
R724
174.2–dc23
2013006628
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
Cover design by www.cyandesign.co.uk
Nicholas Agar, Ph.D., is Reader in Philosophy at Victoria University of Wellington, New Zealand. He is interested in ethical issues arising out of human enhancement. His most recent book on this topic is Humanity’s End: Why We Should Reject Radical Enhancement (2010).
Richard J. Arneson, Ph.D., holds the Valtz Family Chair in Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy at the University of California, San Diego. His recent current research is on distributive justice. Some of this work explores how one might best incorporate a reasonable account of personal responsibility into a broadly egalitarian theory of justice. He also considers how consequentialist morality (one ought always to do an act the consequences of which are no worse than those of any alternative available act) might be developed in a version that is appealing and appropriately responsive to its critics. This latter project involves exploring the structure of moderate deontology to identify the best rival of consequentialism.
Robert Arp, Ph.D., is author of Scenario Visualization: An Evolutionary Account of Creative Problem Solving (2008), co-editor with George Terzis of Information and Living Systems: Philosophical and Scientific Perspectives (2011), co-editor with Francisco Ayala of Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology (Wiley-Blackwell, 2009), and co-editor with Alex Rosenberg of Philosophy of Biology: An Anthology (Wiley-Blackwell, 2009), and he has interests in bioethics as well. He works as a data analyst and modeler (see www.robertarp.webs.com).
Tom L. Beauchamp, Ph.D., is Professor of Philosophy and Senior Research Scholar, Kennedy Institute of Ethics, Georgetown University. His research interests are in the ethics of human-subjects research, the ethics of animal-subjects research and human uses of animals, the place of universal principles and rights in biomedical ethics, methods of bioethics, Hume and the history of modern philosophy, and business ethics.
James L. Bernat, M.D., is the Louis and Ruth Frank Professor of Neuroscience, and Professor of Neurology and Medicine at the Geisel School of Medicine at Dartmouth. He is a neurologist at Dartmouth-Hitchcock Medical Center where he directs the program in clinical ethics. bernat@dartmouth.edu.
Edwin Black is the award-winning, New York Times-bestselling and international investigative author of 80 award-winning editions in 14 languages in 65 countries, as well as scores of newspaper and magazine articles in the leading publications of the United States, Europe, and Israel. With more than a million books in print, his work focuses on genocide and hate, corporate criminality and corruption, governmental misconduct, academic fraud, philanthropic abuse, oil addiction, alternative energy, and historical investigation. For his award-winning eugenic work, War Against the Weak: Eugenics and America’s Campaign to Create a Master Race, he has received the Justice for All Award, the International Human Rights Award, and numerous other citations.
Catherine M. Brooks, J.D., is a professor of law at Creighton University in Omaha, Nebraska, specializing in children’s and family law. She is the co-founder of the Creighton Center for the Study of Children’s Issues and co-editor of the Nebraska Juvenile Court Procedures Manual. She has numerous publications in peer-reviewed journals and law reviews. Professor Brooks provides consultations to family law practitioners, child advocacy groups, and other social-service organizations, particularly in matters involving child custody disputes and child protection. She earned her law degree from the University of Virginia and her bachelor’s and master’s degrees from Thomas More College of Fordham University and the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Fordham University. Her current work focuses on the use of mediation and negotiation in resolving disputes within families and between families and state protection agencies.
Arthur L. Caplan, Ph.D., is the Drs William F. and Virginia Connolly Mitty Professor and founding head of the Division of Bioethics at New York University Langone Medical Center in New York City. Prior to coming to NYU, he was the Sidney D. Caplan Professor of Bioethics at the University of Pennsylvania Perelman School of Medicine in Philadelphia where he created the Center for Bioethics and the Department of Medical Ethics. He is the author or editor of 30 books and over 550 papers in refereed journals. His most recent books are Smart Mice Not So Smart People (2006) and the Penn Guide to Bioethics (2009).
Mark J. Cherry, Ph.D., is the Dr Patricia A. Hayes Professor in Applied Ethics and Professor of Philosophy at St. Edward’s University. He earned his undergraduate degree in philosophy from the University of Houston and his doctorate degree in philosophy from Rice University in Houston, Texas. His research compasses ethics and bioethics, together with social and political philosophy. He is author of Kidney for Sale by Owner: Human Organs, Transplantation and the Market (2005) as well as editor of The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, associate senior editor of Christian Bioethics, Editor-in-Chief of HealthCare Ethics Committee Forum, co-editor of the book series The Annals of Bioethics, and editor of the book series Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture.
Winston Chiong, M.D., Ph.D., is a clinical fellow in the University of California, San Francisco Department of Neurology, and is a postdoctoral research fellow in the Helen Wills Neuroscience Institute at the University of California, Berkeley. His current research encompasses neuroscientific and conceptual methods to investigate changes in decision-making, moral agency, and personhood in the context of neurological illness.
Carl Cohen, Ph.D., is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan, and co-author (with Tom Regan) of The Animal Rights Debate (2001). He was for years a member of the Animal Care and Use Committee of the Pfizer Corporation, and has served for decades on the Institutional Review Board of the University of Michigan Medical Center in Ann Arbor.
Kevin S. Decker, Ph.D., is Associate Professor of Philosophy and Associate Dean of the College of Arts and Letters at Eastern Washington University near Spokane, Washington. His areas of research interest include American pragmatism, social and political theory, and applied ethics. He is the co-editor of three books on philosophy and popular culture.
Katrien Devolder, Ph.D., is Senior Research Fellow at Bioethics Institute Ghent at Ghent University. Her research interests include medical ethics (in particular, the ethics of cloning), stem-cell research, genetic selection, chemical castration, and medical complicity in others’ wrongdoing.
Jason T. Eberl, Ph.D., is Associate Professor and Graduate Director of Philosophy in the Indiana University School of Liberal Arts at Indiana University-Purdue University, Indianapolis. He is also an affiliate faculty member of the IU Center for Bioethics and the IUPUI Medical Humanities & Health Studies program. He has published articles and reviews in American Journal of Bioethics, Bioethics, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly, and Linacre Quarterly. His book Thomistic Principles and Bioethics was published in 2006.
John Geyman, M.D., is Professor Emeritus of Family Medicine at the University of Washington School of Medicine, where he chaired the Department of Family Medicine from 1976 to 1990. He has also practiced family medicine in rural communities for 13 years, edited family-medicine journals for 30 years, served as president of Physicians for a National Health Program from 2005 to 2007, and is a member of the Institute of Medicine. His books include The Corporate Transformation of Health Care: Can the Public Interest Still Be Served? (2004), The Corrosion of Medicine: Can the Profession Reclaim Its Moral Legacy? (2008), and Health Care Wars: How Market Ideology and Corporate Power Are Killing Americans (2012).
Jean Kazez, Ph.D., is Adjunct Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Southern Methodist University. She is the author of Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals (2010) and The Weight of Things: Philosophy and the Good Life (2007), both published by Wiley-Blackwell.
David Koepsell, Ph.D., earned his law degree and Ph.D. in philosophy from the University at Buffalo. He teaches ethics in the Philosophy Section, Faculty of Values and Technology, Delft University of Technology, The Netherlands. He has published widely on the philosophy of intellectual property, applied ethics, ontology, and civil rights (see http://davidkoepsell.com).
John Lachs, Ph.D., is Centennial Professor of Philosophy at Vanderbilt University. His latest book, Stoic Pragmatism (Indiana University Press), has just appeared.
Patrick Lee, Ph.D., holds the John N. and Jamie D. McAleer Chair of Bioethics, and is the Director of the Institute of Bioethics, at Franciscan University of Steubenville. He has published widely on bioethics, including written articles and books on bioethics, including Body-Self Dualism in Contemporary Ethics and Politics (with Robert P. George, 2007), Abortion and Unborn Human Life (2010).
Stephen E. Levick, M.D., is a clinical assistant professor of psychiatry at the University of Pennsylvania School of Medicine, where he supervises psychotherapy, and has his own private practice nearby. His book, Clone Being: Exploring the Psychological and Social Dimensions (2004), was described by cloning pioneer, Ian Wilmut, as “the first framework for detailed analysis of the ethical, psychological, and social consequences of human reproductive cloning.” He employs arguments generated from that framework as both siege engines and battlements in his debate with Dr Devolder on the issue in this volume.
Jane Maienschein, Ph.D., is Regents’ Professor, President’s Professor, and Parents Association Professor at Arizona State University, where she serves as Director of the Center for Biology and Society. She is also Adjunct Scientist and Director of the History and Philosophy of Science Program at the Marine Biological Laboratory in Woods Hole, Massachusetts. An MBL-ASU/HPS collaboration includes the Embryo Project (embryo.mbl.edu), HPS Repository, and Digital HPS Consortium. She is (co)editor of a dozen books and author of three, including Whose View of Life? Embryos, Cloning, and Stem Cells with Harvard University Press.
Bertha Alvarez Manninen, Ph.D., is an associate professor of philosophy at Arizona State University’s West campus. Her primary area of research is bioethics with an emphasis on the moral status of embryos and fetuses. Other interests include philosophy of religion, ancient philosophy, social and political philosophy, and philosophy and film.
Don Marquis, Ph.D., is Professor of Philosophy at The University of Kansas. His essay “Why Abortion is Immoral” was published in The Journal of Philosophy in 1989 and has been reprinted over 90 times.
Daryl Pullman, Ph.D., is a professor of medical ethics in the Faculty of Medicine, at Memorial University in Newfoundland and Labrador, Canada. He has published widely on issues in clinical and research ethics.
Laura Purdy, Ph.D., is Professor Emerita of Philosophy at Wells College. Her research has focused primarily on issues in reproduction and family.
Jeffrey Reiman, Ph.D., is the William Fraser McDowell Professor of Philosophy at American University in Washington, DC. He is the author of In Defense of Political Philosophy (Harper & Row, 1972), Justice and Modern Moral Philosophy (1990), Critical Moral Liberalism: Theory and Practice (1997), The Death Penalty: For and Against (with Louis Pojman, 1998), Abortion and the Ways We Value Human Life (1999), The Rich Get Richer and the Poor Get Prison: Ideology, Class, and Criminal Justice (with Paul Leighton, 2012), As Free and As Just as Possible: The Theory of Marxian Liberalism (Wiley-Blackwell, 2012), and more than 120 articles in philosophy and criminal justice journals and anthologies.
Lawrence M. Sung, J.D., Ph.D., is a Partner with the law firm of Baker & Hostetler LLP in the Washington, DC office, specializing in biotechnology, pharmaceutical, and medical device patent litigation, counseling, and technology transfer. Dr Sung is also a professor and the Director of the Intellectual Property Law Program at the University of Maryland School of Law in Baltimore, MD. He may be contacted at lsung@bakerlaw.com or lsung@law.umaryland.edu.
Christopher Tollefsen, Ph.D., is Professor of Philosophy at the University of South Carolina; he has twice been a visiting fellow in the James Madison Program at Princeton University. He has published over 60 articles, book chapters, and reviews on bioethics and natural law ethics, and is the author, co-author, or editor of five recent books, including Biomedical Research and Beyond: Expanding the Ethics of Inquiry (2012) and, with Robert P. George, Embryo: A Defense of Human Life (2011). He has recently completed a book manuscript, provisionally titled Truth, Lies, and the Natural Law: Why Lying for a Good Cause is Always Wrong. Tollefsen sits on the editorial board of a number of journals and is the editor of the Springer book series, Catholic Studies in Bioethics.
Jamie Carlin Watson, Ph.D., is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Young Harris College (Young Harris, GA). With Robert Arp, he is the author of Critical Thinking: An Introduction to Reasoning Well (2011), Philosophy DeMYSTiFied (2011), and What’s Good on TV: Understanding Ethics Through Television (Wiley-Blackwell, 2011). He is currently working with Peter Fosl and Galen Foresman on The Critical Thinker’s Toolkit (Wiley-Blackwell).
Glen Whitman, Ph.D., is a professor of economics at California State University, Northridge and an adjunct scholar with the Cato Institute. He received his Ph.D. in economics from New York University in 2000. His research in applied game theory, economic analysis of law, and economic methodology has appeared in the Journal of Legal Studies, UCLA Law Review, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, and other scholarly journals. His current research interests include healthcare and paternalistic legislation.
William J. Winslade, J.D., Ph.D., Ph.D., is James Wade Rockwell Professor of Philosophy of Medicine, Professor of Preventive Medicine and Community Health, and Professor of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, and is a member of the Institute for the Medical Humanities at the University of Texas Medical Branch, Galveston, Texas. He is also Distinguished Visiting Professor of Law at the University of Houston Health Law and Policy Institute. Philosophic, legal, and psychoanalytic ideas are applied in his work to the study of human values in science, medicine, technology, and law. His book Confronting Traumatic Brain Injury: Devastation, Hope and Healing was published in 1998. He has co-authored three other books: Clinical Ethics: A Practical Approach to Ethical Decisions in Clinical Medicine, Sixth Edition (2006), written for health professionals; The Insanity Plea: The Uses and Abuses of The Insanity Defense (1983), written for a general audience; and Choosing Life and Death (1986), written for patients and their families as well as health professionals about medical–moral–legal–technological topics such as kidney dialysis, organ transplantation, treatment or non-treatment of damaged newborns, termination of life support, genetic screening and counseling, and healthcare costs and policies. In addition, he has written numerous scholarly articles and essays for general readers on topics such as privacy and confidentiality, human rights, death and dying, and legal and ethical aspects of mental-health practice. He is currently working on a book with Stacey Tovino, J.D., Ph.D., tentatively titled The Birth Life and Death of the Brain: Legal and Ethical Perspectives.
Art wants to acknowledge the support of the New York University Langone Medical Center and its Dean, Robert Grossman, in giving him the opportunity to complete this book. Rob acknowledges the support of Jeff Dean at Wiley-Blackwell, who believed in the project in the first place.
This book features chapters written by contemporary scholars doing work in the central topics of the branch of applied ethics known as bioethics. The chapters are presented in a debate style with yes and no responses—often qualified—to core contemporary quandaries in the field. The book is intended to provoke discussion and debate for students in ethics, bioethics, and medical ethics classrooms in high school, college, and professional school.
The English word “bioethics” comes from two Greek words: bios (βίος) meaning “life” and ethikos (ἠθικός) meaning “displaying moral character.” In 1927, Fritz Jahr used the term in an article, “Bio-Ethik: Eine Umschau über die ethischen Beziehungen des Menschen zu Tier und Pflanze,” which can be translated as “Bio-Ethics: A Review of the Ethical Relationships of Humans to Animals and Plants” (Jahr, 1927; Sass, 2007; Goldim, 2009). In that article, Jahr wanted to extend a “bioethical imperative” to all forms of life, arguing that we ought to treat other humans and living things with respect as ends in and of themselves (Kant, 1785/1998). In 1971, Van Rensselaer Potter also used the term in his book, Bioethics: Bridge to the Future (Potter, 1971). He subsequently wrote Global Bioethics: Building on the Leopold Legacy, and in 1995 co-authored the article, “Global Bioethics: Converting Sustainable Development to Global Survival” (Potter, 1971, 1988; Potter & Potter, 1995). For both Jahr and Potter, what they referred to as “bioethics” would be considered today to be the related branch of applied ethics known as environmental ethics. This area of ethics explores our relationship to the natural world, our duties to preserve and protect nature, and whether morality extends beyond humans to animals, other living things, and the entire biosphere itself (Attfield, 2003; Keller, 2010).
Bioethics, while keenly aware of the ways in which health is shaped by climate and the environment, is focused today mainly on humans and the issues that emerge in conducting biomedical and clinical research, healthcare, and the policies that ought to govern medicine, nursing, allied health, and the related biomedical sciences (Caplan, 1992b, 1994, 1997, 1998, 2009; Jonsen et al., 2011). So, while the name “bioethics” derives from scholars seeking to create environmental ethics, the history of bioethics is actually rooted in medical ethics, a branch of applied ethics concerned with the practice of medicine and healthcare (Ramsey, 1970; Katz, 1984; Veatch, 1989, 2011; Pellegrino, 2008; Kuhse & Singer, 2009; Pence, 2010). Given the close connection between bioethics and medical ethics, some refer to the discipline as biomedical ethics (Beauchamp & Childress, 1979/2009; also Glannon, 2004; Mappes & DeGrazia, 2005).
Bioethics has a subject matter and specific questions that it has developed near the end of the twentieth century, and the topics that comprise this subject matter include:
Most of these topics are debated by the contributors to this book. Each core topic is described further in the introductions to each section, including relevant reading material. The reader should consult various other resources in bioethics to get a sense of the scope and breadth of view on the core topics such as:
Edited books and encyclopedias:
Journals:
Bioethics centers maintain websites with useful information, including:
The core topics of bioethics oftentimes emerged as a result of the moral outcry elicited by some highly publicized practice, event, or series of events in biomedicine or clinical research that actually (or potentially) harmed people, animals, or even the biosphere. In this respect, the topics in bioethics are no different than any ethical topic that has emerged in the course of human history (Cavalier et al., 1989; MacIntyre, 1998).
For example, the Nazi experimentation on humans that took place between 1939 and 1945, where people were subjected to various hazardous and horrific experiments often designed to assist in the advancement of military medicine and the physician-directed racial euthanasia campaigns of the Nazis, raised many questions about the ethics of those involved (Caplan, 1992a; Conot, 1993; Annas & Grodin, 1995; Lifton, 2000; Spitz, 2005). During and after the Nuremberg trials (1946–1949), where numerous Nazis were tried for a variety of atrocious crimes, the Nuremberg Code was devised and codified in response to the systematic abuse of human subjects in research. The Code, which was in reality the decision in one of the trials of German doctors, includes basic biomedical principles related to human experimentation (clinical research) such as absence of coercion in recruiting subjects, the necessity of informed consent, non-maleficence toward participants in experiments, and the correct formulation of a scientific protocol (Weindling, 2004; Schmidt & Frewer, 2007; NIH, 2011a).
It would seem that anyone who lived during the middle of the twentieth century and was made aware of the Nazi human experimentation would sympathize with the Jewish slogan that refers to the atrocities of the Holocaust and murder fueled by racism and anti-Semitism: Never Again! However, the US and the world were shocked to hear in 1972 that, for 40 years, an experiment monitoring the effects of syphilis upon poor, rural, and illiterate African-American men—who, having been lied to by researchers, thought they were being treated for the disease but in fact were not—had been conducted by the US Public Health Service and Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. The Tuskegee Syphilis Experiment—so named because Tuskegee Institute was a willing participant—began as an observational study in 1932 with 600 African-American men, 399 with syphilis and 201 without the disease. In 1972, when the study became known through whistle-blowing in the media, 74 of the 600 men were still alive. Concerning the original 399 men with syphilis, 28 died of syphilis, and 100 died of syphilis-related complications, while 40 of their wives were infected with syphilis, and 19 of their children were born with syphilis (Jones, 1992; Reverby, 2009). What makes this experiment all the more insidious is the fact that, by 1945, penicillin was being mass-produced in the US to treat diseases like syphilis, and the infected men in the experiment easily could have been treated after 1945; and many lives would have been saved as well as much pain and suffering avoided (Katz & Warren, 2011).
In response to the Tuskegee Syphilis Experiment as well as increased public awareness of other unethical experiments conducted in the US and in other countries (Beecher, 1966), in 1974 the National Research Act (Pub. L. 93-348) of the US established the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research (1974–1978), and in 1979 the Commission issued a landmark document for biomedicine or clinical research called, “The Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research.” It was named “The Belmont Report” for the Smithsonian Institution’s Belmont Conference Center (Elkridge, MD) where the Commission met in February of 1976 when first drafting the report (Childress et al., 2005; NIH, 2011b). The Belmont Report affirmed all of the basic bioethical principles found in the Nuremberg Code, as well as articulated other principles, including the principle of justice whereby “equals ought to be treated equally.” The report called for peer review of all studies to insure that the risk/benefit ratio involved made moral sense and that the informed consent of subjects was adequate. Unfortunately, there are numerous cases of unethical human experimentation documented in the US and other countries throughout the twentieth century, and these cases form the basis for a central topic in bioethics (Moreno, 2000; Dresser, 2001; Goliszek, 2003; Guerrini, 2003; the papers in Hawkins & Emanuel, 2008).
Scandal was not the only driver of bioethics. Controversy plays a key role in the development of the field as well. Although abortion has been practiced by numerous cultures throughout human history and even can be traced to a Chinese medical text from the reign of Shen Nung (2737–2696 BCE), and although it is true that, by 1970, scholars had already been debating the abortion issue as a result of increased recognition of women’s reproductive rights, improvement in abortion technology, many ER instances of bungled backroom abortions, and the American Medical Association’s call to decriminalize abortion in the US (Noonan, 1970; Thomson, 1971; Warren, 1973), it was the landmark decision by the US Supreme Court to disallow many state and federal restrictions on abortion in Roe v. Wade (410 US 113) in 1973 that brought bioethical attention to the abortion issue (Jonsen, 1998; Joffe, 2009). And with that attention, another topic in bioethics was solidified.
Technological innovation has also driven the emergence of bioethics. Although Willem Kolff is credited with inventing the first kidney-dialysis machine (he also helped invent the artificial heart and heart–lung machine, as well as invented an artificial eye and ear, and the intra-aortic balloon pump), it was Belding Scribner who improved upon Kolff’s machine and opened the first center devoted to dialysis, the Seattle Artificial Kidney Center, in 1962 (Pietzman, 2007; Brown, 2009). Since there were a limited number of machines in the center and many more patients who needed dialysis in order to live, ethical questions related to who should receive dialysis emerged immediately (Jonsen, 2000, pp. 104–106; also Katz & Capron, 1982; Emanuel, 1991; Elger et al., 2008).
Harvard medical researchers, Philip Drinker and Louis Agassiz Shaw, invented the “iron lung” in 1927 to assist or restart breathing in individuals; but even with John Emerson’s improvements on the mechanism in 1931, iron lungs were big, bulky, and expensive to operate. Simple, hand-operated, bag valve mask ventilators began to be used by doctors and others in 1953; but they suffered from the obvious problem of having to be constantly squeezed by someone (Gorman, 1979; Laurie, 2002; Ambu, 2011). In 1971, Siemens introduced the medical world to a small, fairly quiet electronic ventilator—the SERVO 900—and various models soon became a staple in ERs, then in ambulances, too (Maquet Critical Care, 2001, 2005). The electronic ventilator now could be used to assist someone in their breathing, potentially indefinitely, and this occurred regularly for people in comas. The extended use of a ventilator (usually in combination with a feeding tube) has been the source of much debate, and cases of people in persistent vegetative states requiring ventilators and feeding tubes—such as the widely publicized cases of Karen Ann Quinlan, who lived with a feeding tube in a persistent vegetative state from 1975 to 1985, and Terri Schiavo, who lived with a feeding tube in a persistent vegetative state from 1990 to 2005—cause people to think about the extent to which these biomedical technologies are ethically appropriate or not (Armstrong & Colen, 1988; Buchanan & Brock, 1990; Caplan et al., 2006).